Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 84))

  • 382 Accesses

Abstract

In light of what we have seen in our previous chapter, what can be said of SR’s putative elimination of metaphysical time and space?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Lawrence Sklar, “Time, reality and relativity,” in Reduction, Time and Reality,ed. Richard Healey (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See the excellent survey in Frederick Suppe, “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories,” in The Structure of Scientific Theories, 2d ed., ed. F. Suppe (Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois Press, 1977 ), pp. 3–118.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Tyler Burge, “Philosophy of Language and Mind,” Philosophical Review 101 (1992): 49.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Richard Healey, “Introduction,” in Reduction, Time and Reality,p. vii.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Richard F. Kitchener, “Introduction: The World View of Contemporary Physics: Does It Need a New Metaphysics?” in The World View of Contemporary Physics, ed. Richard F. Kitchener ( Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988 ), p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  7. M. Laue, “Zwei Einwände gegen die Relativitätstheorie und ihre Widerlegung,” Physikalische Zeitschrift 13 (1912): 120.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Richard Swinburne, “Verificationism and Theories of Spacetime,” in Space, Time, and Causality, ed. Richard Swinburne, Synthèse Library 157 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1983), p. 63. He aptly remarks, “A satisfactory science ought to reveal the extent of our ignorance, not pretend that what is not knowable is not true” (Ibid., p. 74). Stating that “chrw(133)I know of no good argument for verificationism,” Swinburne contends that there is “no need to follow Einstein in his verificationism” (Richard Swinburne, Space and Time, 2d ed. [London: Macmillan, 1981], pp. 6, 201 ).

    Google Scholar 

  9. John D. Norton, “Philosophy of Space and Time,” in Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, ed. Merilee Salmon (New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, 1992 ), p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  10. E. A. Milne, “Presidential Address to the Royal Astronomical Society,” Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 104 (1944): 121.

    Google Scholar 

  11. P. J. Zwart, “The Flow of Time,” Synthèse 24 (1972): 134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Mary F. Cleugh, Time and its Importance in Modern Thought, with a Foreword by L. Susan Stebbing (London: Methuen, 1937 ), pp. 29–30, 61.

    Google Scholar 

  13. James Jeans, Physics and Philosophy (Cambridge: University Press, 1942), p. 68; cf. p. 66. Some theorists have disputed the reduction of time to its measures but have gratuitously assumed that time is that quantity described by relativity theory. See, for example, the critique of operational definitions of time by Mario Bunge, “Physical Time: The Objective and Relational Theory,” Philosophy of Science 35 (1968): 355–388, though Bunge’s concept of time is still physical, not metaphysical, in that it is analyzed as a map from sets of events, reference frames, and chronometric scales to the real numbers; see also Henry Mehlberg, Time, Causality, and the Quantum Theory,2 vols., ed. Robert S. Cohen, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1980), 1: 1, 189–190, 251, who thinks that physical time is but an aspect of universal time and yet seems to assume that universal time is relativistic.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ralph Baierlein, Newton to Einste in: The Trail of Light ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992 ), p. 215.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Cleugh, Time,p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Hermann Bondi, Relativity and Common Sense ( New York: Dover Publications, 1964 ), p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  18. C. Moller, The Theory of Relativity, 2d ed. ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1972 ), p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Heinz Pagels, The Cosmic Code ( London: Michael Joseph, 1982 ), p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Clifford M. Will, Was Einstein Right? ( New York: Basic Books, 1986 ), pp. 49–50.

    Google Scholar 

  21. M. Capek, “The Inclusion of Becoming in the Physical World,” in The Concepts of Space and Time,ed. Milic Capek, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976), p. 520; cf his verificationist remarks that “the succession of causally unrelated events” is devoid of physical meaning, so that the simultaneity of distant events and the succession of causally independent events simply do not exist (Ibid., pp. 514–515).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Julian B. Barbour, Absolute or Relative Motion?, vol. 1: The Discovery of Dynamics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989 ), pp. 8–9.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Yehudah Freundlich, “;‘Becoming’ and the Asymmetries of Time,” Philosophy of Science 40 (1973): 497–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Michael C. Duffy, “The Modified Vortex Sponge: a Classical Analogue for General Relativity,” paper presented at the International Conference of the British Society for the Philosophy of Science, “Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory,” Imperial College of Science and Technology, London, 16–19 September, 1988. He quotes with approval H. P. Robertson’s remark, “Ives had in fact set up a theory completely equivalent in substance to the special theory of relativitychrw(133)but I was never able to convince him that since what he had was in fact indistinguishable in its predictions from the relativity theory within the domain of physics, it waschrw…the same theorychrw….” Ives was apparently the keener epistemologist of the two.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ray d’Invemo, Introducing Einstein’s Relativity ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992 ), p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  26. P. C. W. Davies, Space and Time in the Modern Universe ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977 ), p. 160.

    Google Scholar 

  27. P. C. W. Davies, God and the New Physics ( New York: Simon & Schuster, 1983 ), pp. 38–39.

    Google Scholar 

  28. C. Misner, K. S. Thorne, and J. A. Wheeler, Gravitation (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1973), p. 1183. Cf. Wheeler’s declaration, “There is no such thing as spacetime in the real world of quantum physicschrw(133)superspace leaves us space but not spacetime and therefore not time. With time gone the very ideas of ‘before’ and ‘after’ also lose their meaning” (J. A. Wheeler, “From Relativity to Mutability,” in The Physicist’s Conception of Nature, ed. J. Mehra [Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1973 ], p. 227 ).

    Google Scholar 

  29. T. Banks, “TCP, Quantum Gravity, the Cosmological Constant, and All Thatchrw(133),” Nuclear Physics B 249 (1985): 340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Henry Mehlberg, “Philosophical Aspects of Physical Time, ” Monist 53 (1969): 363.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler, Gravitation,p. 823.

    Google Scholar 

  32. James Hartle and Stephen W. Hawking, “Wave Function of the Universe,” Physical Review D 28 (1983): 2960–2975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Stephen W. Hawking, A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes,with an Introduction by Carl Sagan (New York: Bantam Books, 1988), pp. 14, 35.

    Google Scholar 

  34. C. J. Isham, “Creation of the Universe as a Quantum Process,” in Physics, Philosophy, and Theology: A Common Quest for Understanding, ed. R. J. Russell, W. R. Stoeger, and G. V. Coyne (Vatican City: Vatican Observatory, 1988), pp. 376, 391, 399, 402–403.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Adolf Grünbaum, Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, 2d ed., Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 12 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1973 ), pp. 197–201.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  36. Arthur Pap, Introduction to the Philosophy of Science ( London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1963 ), pp. 9798.

    Google Scholar 

  37. M. Capek, “Introduction,” in The Concepts of Space and Time,ed. M. Capek, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976), p. xxx.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Carlo Rovelli, “What Does Present Days [sic] Physics Tell Us about Time and Space?” Lecture presented at the Annual Series Lectures of the Center for Philosophy of Science of the University of Pittsburgh, 17 September 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Julian B. Barbour, “The Timelessness of Quantum Gravity: I & II,” Classical and Quantum Gravity 11 (1994): 2853–2873, 2875–2897. Barbour holds that instants exist, but these are analyzed as three-dimensional relative configurations of the universe in superspace.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Jonathan Powers, Philosophy and the New Physics, Ideas (London: Methuen, 1982 ), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Peter Kroes, Time: Its Structure and Role in Physical Theories,Synthèse Library 179 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1985), p. xiii; cf. p. viii.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid., p. 196.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid., p. xxiv [my emphasis]; cf. p. 209.

    Google Scholar 

  44. See also Herbert Dingle, “Time in Philosophy and Physics,” Philosophy 54 (1979): 99–104. Though overly generous to Einstein in stating that —time, “the ever-rolling stream, never entered his thoughts” in the 1905 paper, Dingle is correct that Einstein’s theory had only to do with clock-times and proved nothing about the nature of time itself. Cf. idem, Science at the Crossroads ( London: Martin Brian & O’Keefe, 1972 ), p. 137.

    Google Scholar 

  45. H. Margenau, “Metaphysical Elements in Physics,” Reviews of Modern Physics 13 (1941): 183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Philipp Frank, Interpretations and Misinterpretations of Modern Physics, Actualités Scientifiques et Industrielles 587: Exposés de Philosophie Scientifique 2 (Paris: Hermann & Cie., 1938 ), p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Philipp Frank, Philosophy of Science (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, 1957 ), p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Arthur Eddington, Space, Time and Gravitation, Cambridge Science Classics (1920; rep. ed.: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987 ), p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Arthur Eddington, The Nature of the Physical World,with an Introductory Note by Sir Edmund Whittaker, Everyman’s Library (1928; rep. ed.: London: J. M. Dent & Sons, 1964), p.47; so also S. C. Tiwari, “Fresh Look on Relativistic Time and Lifetime of an Unstable Particle,” paper presented at the International Conference of the British Society for the Philosophy of Science, “Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory,” Imperial College of Science and Technology, London, 16–19 September, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Herbert Dingle, “Time in Relativity Theory: Measurement or Coordinate?” in The Voices of Time, 2d ed., ed. with a new Introduction by J. T. Fraser ( Amherst, Mass.: University of Massachusetts Press, 1981 ), p. 462.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cleugh, Time,p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Albert Einstein, The Meaning of Relativity, 6th ed., (1922; rep. ed.: London: Chapman & Hall, 1967 ), p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  53. T. Sjödin, “On the One-Way Velocity of Light and its Possible Measurability,” paper presented at “Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory.” See also Richard Gale, “Human Time: Introduction,” in The Philosophy of Time: a Collection of Essays,ed. R. M. Gale (New York: Humanities Press, 1968), p. 299; M. Capek, The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics (Princeton: D. Van Nostrand, 1961), p. 172. It is noteworthy that the Galilean transformations follow automatically from the Lorentz equations if we substitute for can infinite value.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Sjödin, “One-Way Velocity of Light.”

    Google Scholar 

  55. SR prohibits the acceleration of particles from subluminal to luminal or superluminal speeds, not particles that always travel at such speeds. SR may also be incompatible with superluminal signals (controllable causal connections), but nothing in Sjödin’s definition depends on the use of signals as opposed to raw tachyon beams occurring naturally.

    Google Scholar 

  56. See the discussion and literature listed in Craig, Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Grünbaum, Space and Time,p. 827.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Michael Friedman, Foundations of Spacetime Theories ( Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983 ), p. 167.

    Google Scholar 

  59. See Wesley C. Salmon, Space, Time, and Motion ( Encino, Calif.: Dickenson Publishing, 1975 ), pp. 119–122.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Olexa-Myron Bilaniuk, et al.,“More about Tachyons,” Physics Today,(December 1969): 52.

    Google Scholar 

  61. See, for example, Michael Redhead, “Nonlocality and Peaceful Coexistence,” in Space, Time and Causality, ed. Richard Swinburne, Synthèse Library 157 (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1983), pp. 167–179; idem, “The Conventionality of Simultaneity,” in Philosophical Problems of the Internal and External Worlds, ed. John Eannan, Alan I. Janis, Gerald J. Massey, and Nicholas Rescher, Pittsburgh-Konstanz Series in the Philosophy and History of Science (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1993), pp. 116–125; Graham Nerlich, What Spacetime Explains ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994 ), pp. 68–71.

    Google Scholar 

  62. See Craig, Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom,pp. 122–127.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Gerald Holton, “On the Origins of the Special Theory of Relativity,” in Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein, by Gerald Holton (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1973), pp. 170–171. Dugas comments, “We shall not go as far to complain, as certain critics do, that Einstein made use of magical clocks and enchanted measuring rods in order to retum, in the last analysis, to Lorentz’s transformation (T). But there is no doubt that those ideal clocks and rods can only be used in idealised experiments” (René Dugas, A History of Mechanics, with a Foreword by Louis de Broglie, trans. 1. R. Maddox [New York: Central Book Company, 1955 ], p. 490 ).

    Google Scholar 

  64. Cleugh, Time,p. 59. She asserts, “chrw(133)the simultaneity with which Einstein deals is only a very distant cousin of the simultaneity with which the plain man and the metaphysician are concernedchrw(133),” and, she might have added, the classical physicist as well (p. 58).

    Google Scholar 

  65. Friedman, “Simultaneity,” pp. 411–415.

    Google Scholar 

  66. G. Builder, “The Constancy of the Velocity of Light,” Australian Journal of Physics 11 (1958): 457–480, rep. in Speculations in Science and Technology 2 (1979): 421.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Frank, Philosophy of Science,p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Sklar, “Time, reality, and relativity,” p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Craig, W.L. (2001). The Elimination of Absolute Time. In: Craig, W.L. (eds) Time and the Metaphysics of Relativity. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 84. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3532-2_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3532-2_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5602-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3532-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics