Skip to main content

Simultaneous Causation

  • Chapter
Book cover Time and Cause

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy ((PSSP,volume 19))

Abstract

Consider the following claims about causal simultaneity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Richard Taylor, Action and Purpose, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1966, pp. 9–39, esp. pp. 35–39.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Richard Taylor, `Causation’, Monist47 (1963), 287–313, esp. pp. 303–313, reprinted in Myles Brand (ed.), The Nature of Causation, University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 1976, pp. 277–305; and Bertrand Russell, `On the Notion of Cause’, in Mysticism and Logic, Doubleday, Garden City, N.Y., 1917.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Wesley Sahnon, `An “At-At” Theory of Causal Influence’, Philosophy of Science 44

    Google Scholar 

  4. 215–224; Patrick Suppes, A Probabilistic Theory of Causality, North-Holland Publishing, Amsterdam, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For reviews of historical and contemporary attempts to account for causal asymmetry, see Myles Brand, `Causality’, in P. Asquith and H. E. Kyburg, Jr. (eds.), Current Research in Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, Mich., 1979; and Richard Taylor, `Causation’ in Paul Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 8 vols., Macmillan and Free Press, New York, 1967, Vol. 2, pp. 56–66.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Action and Purpose, pp. 35–36.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See, for example, Taylor’s discussions in Monist, and Action and Purpose; and J. L. Mackie, `Causes and Conditions’, American Philosophical Quarterly 2(1965), 245-264, reprinted, among other places, in Brand (ed.), op. cit., pp. 307-344. Cf. Jaegwon Kim, `Causes and Events_ Mackie on Causation’, Journal of Philosophy 68(1971), 426 - 441.

    Google Scholar 

  8. For a survey of these views, see Mackie, The Cement of the Universe, Oxford University Press, London, 1974, Chap. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Donald Davidson, `Causal Relations’, Journal of Philosophy 64(1967), 691–703, reprinted, among other places, in Brand (ed.), op. cit., pp. 354–367; and `The Individuation of Events’, in N. Rescher et al. (eds.), Essay in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1970, pp. 216-234.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Encyclopedia of Philosophy, p. 65; Taylor makes the same point in Monist, p. 309 and Action and Purpose, pp. 35–36.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Monist, p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Action and Purpose, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  13. A Treatise of Human Nature 1.3.2, ed. by L. A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford University Press, London, 1888, p. 76. For an interesting interpretation of this argument, see Stanley Munsat, ‘Hume’s Argument That Causes Must Precede Their Effects’, Philosophical Studies 22 (1971), 24–26.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Taylor uses a similar example. Suppose that a person is holding a pencil, then the movement of his hand causes the movement of the pencil. See: Action and Purpose, p. 36; Encyclopedia of Philosophy, p. 65; Monist, pp. 309–310.

    Google Scholar 

  15. It is difficult to see how, for instance, an increasing gravitational field can be construed as involving material objects. The cause of such an event might well involve material objects, but the event of the field’s increasing in strength appears devoid of material objects. If events of this sort do not involve material objects, then the view that all events involve material objects, held by Kim and others, is mistaken — cf. Jaegwon Kim, `Events as Property Exemplifications’, in M. Brand and D. Walton (eds.), Action Theory, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1976, pp. 159–177.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Alexander Rosenberg, `Propter Hoc, Ergo post Hoc’, American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (1975), 245–254, esp. pp. 252–253.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Brand, `Particulars, Events and Actions’, in Brand and Walton, op. cit., pp. 135–156; and `Identity Conditions for Events’, American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977), 329–337.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Note that describing events using this canonical form does not commit us to Kim’s view of the internal structure of events. (Actually, Kim’s canonical form is not exactly the one used here; he includes a temporal specification, but not a spatial one.)

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Alvin Goldman, A Theory of Human Action, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., 1970. Judith Jarvis Thomson’s Acts and Other Events, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, N.Y., 1977, contains an extended, original and provocative discussion on parts of events.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Salmon, op. cit., follows Hans Reichenbach in The Direction of Time, ed. by Maria Reichenbach, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1956, esp. Sections 22–23, in using the terms `causal interaction’ and `causal process’. There is considerable difference between my use of the terms and Salmon’s and Reichenbach’s, though there are also some underlying affinities. Some of the differences stem from different notions of events.

    Google Scholar 

  21. For a discussion of Cambridge changes, see Kim, ‘Noncausal Connection’, Noüs8 (1974), 41–52.

    Google Scholar 

  22. I have found helpful the comments of Ralf Meerbote, Marshall Swain, Paul Teller and Irving Thalberg on an early draft. I have also profited by discussing these issues with a number of my colleagues, especially Daniel Berger, and with members of the audiences at the University of Cincinnati, Ohio, and the Somona State Action Theory Conference.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1980 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brand, M. (1980). Simultaneous Causation. In: Van Inwagen, P. (eds) Time and Cause. Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy, vol 19. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8358-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3528-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics