Skip to main content

Tocqueville’s Flight from Doubt and His Search for Certainty: Skepticism in a Democratic Age

  • Chapter
  • 186 Accesses

Abstract

Peter Strawson may be right to suggest that the skeptic voices his doubts as a “challenge to himself—to show that the doubts are unjustified, that the beliefs put in question are justified.”1 Still, I wonder if the aphorism isn’t somewhat overdrawn unless one concedes that the questioning is a continuous mental process: doubts may continue to lurk in the dark, or, under the right conditions, even bask in the sunlight, no matter how strong one’s beliefs are. Alexis de Tocqueville’s ideas on the psychological and political dynamic governing the exercise of religious beliefs in a democratic society in which the future of liberty, both private and public, which was in his view far from assured, may place him between firm beliefs and equally firm doubts. I am proposing to tie two matters together. The first is that skepticism, but skepticism of a special and surprising sort, was an important part of Tocqueville’s intellectual makeup. This becomes evident from a probing of contradictory passages from Tocqueville’s writings. The second is that his encounters with doubt were meaningful for him at two levels. At the first level, his struggles with doubt were existential and often private. At the second, he rarely isolated them from, or failed to integrate them within, the social, political and religious transformations of his time. He often synoptically described them by the term “incredulity” and which he saw even more fundamentally embodied in the notion of moeurs, appropriated from the eighteenth century and earlier. By moeurs, he meant more than the habits of the individual heart. His own words clarify his intentions. “I mean to apply it [the term moeurs] ... to the different notions possessed by man, the various opinions current among them, and the sum of ideas that shape mental habits. So I use the word to cover the whole moral and intellectual state of a people. It is not my aim to describe American mores; just now I am only looking for the elements in them which help to support political institutions.”2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Peter F. Strawson, Skepticism and Naturalism: Some Varieties (New York, 1985), 2.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Alexis de Tocqueville, De la démocratie en Amérique,ed. Eduardo Nolla, 2 vols. (Paris, 1990), 1:223. Hereafter De la démocratie.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Blaise Pascal, Pensées,ed. and tr. Alban J. Krailshaimer (Harmondsworth, 1966), no. 200 (the no. order follows that of the ed. by Louis Lafuma).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Tocqueville to Corcelle, 1 August 1850, Alexis de Tocqueville, Oeuvres, Papiers et Correspondances (Oeuvres Complètes),ed. J.-P. Mayer, 18 vols. (Paris, 1950-), 15/2:29 (hereafter: OC,followed by volume, part, and page number).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Tocqueville to Bouchitté, 8 January 1858, Oeuvres complètes,ed. Gustave de Beaumont, 9 vols., (Paris, 1864–78), 7:175–77.

    Google Scholar 

  6. OC,3/2:551. The emphasis is Tocqueville’s.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Le Commerce,6 December 1844, in OC,3/2:579. 12 Liberté d’enseignement” (no date), ibid., 559.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Sur la liberté religieuse,“ Séance du 28 avril 1845, Moniteur universel du 29 avril 1845, 1130, ibid., 599.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Séance de la chambre des pairs,“ Le Commerce,7 March 1845, ibid., 605.

    Google Scholar 

  10. De la démocratie1:226.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., the citations are to be found on 29, 30, and 35.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Margo Todd, Christian Humanism and the Puritan Social Order (Cambridge, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  13. See T.J. Hochstrasser, “The Claims of Conscience: Natural Law Theory, Obligation, and Resistance in the Huguenot Diaspora,” New Essays on the Political Thought of the Huguenots of the Refuge,ed.

    Google Scholar 

  14. John C. Laursen (Leiden, 1995), 15–51.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Tocqueville to Kergorlay, 29 June 1831, OC, 13 /1: 227–31.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Though not following in Tocqueville’s footsteps, Jeremy Waldron, writing some one hundred and sixty years later, held much the same opinion about the coexistence of religious groups, making the point that modem society is highly self-conscious of the rapid succession of moral outlooks in American society. See Jeremy Waldron, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers, 1981–1991 (Cambridge, 1993 ).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Tocqueville to Gobineau, 22 October 1843, OC,9:57–62, 67–68.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Tocqueville to Gobineau, 5 September 1843, OC, 9: 45.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Tocqueville anticipates in part both Keiji Nishitani, Religion and Nothingness,tr. Jan Van Bragt (Berkeley, 1982) and Mark C. Taylor, Nots (Chicago, 1993), who argue that Cartesian doubt collapses truth into certainty, making truth entirely a subjective matter. In another close reading of Descartes, Richard Tuck, Philosophy and Government, 1572–1651 (Cambridge, UK, 1993), 293, notes that Descartes’ answer to “hyperbolic doubt” was in essence a combination of the cogito argument with proof of God’s existence,“ a solution, Tuck fmds, that deals only with the ”epistemological side of perception,“ and not at all with the moral world.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kergorlay to Tocqueville, 23 June 1832, OC, 13 /1: 257.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Tocqueville to Royer-Collard, 6 April 1838, OC, 11: 59–61.

    Google Scholar 

  22. On ataraxia in its original Pyrrhonian and in its modern contexts, see the opposing views of Myles F. Burnyeat, “Can the Skeptic Live His Skepticism,” The Skeptical Tradition,ed. Burnyeat (Berkeley, 1983), 117–48; and David R. Hiley, “The Deep Challenge of Pyrrhonian Scepticism,” Journal of the History of Philosophy,25 (1987), 185–213, esp. 193–95.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Tocqueville to Kergorlay, 5 August 1836, OC, 13 /1, 389.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Tocqueville to Kergorlay, 2 February 1838, OC, 13 /2: 12.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Tocqueville to Kergorlay, 18 October 1847, OC, 13 /2: 207.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. Charles Taylor, The Malaise of Modernity (Concord, Ont., 1991), who takes up this question, but does not look into the negative consequences of Tocqueville’ s endorsement of competing self-interest groups, though he is hardly unaware that these are the groups that command substantial power in modern political cultures.

    Google Scholar 

  27. For the claim that liberalism cannot be considered apart from its political stance, indeed, that it is primarily a political position, see Stephen Holmes, The Anatomy of Anti-Liberalism ( Cambridge, Mass., 1993 ).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Tocqueville to Gobineau, 5 August 1858, OC, 9: 295.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mitchell, H. (1998). Tocqueville’s Flight from Doubt and His Search for Certainty: Skepticism in a Democratic Age. In: van der Zande, J., Popkin, R.H. (eds) The Skeptical Tradition Around 1800. International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées, vol 155. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3465-3_20

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3465-3_20

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4946-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3465-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics