Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 81))

  • 98 Accesses

Abstract

The last chapter ended with establishment of the guiding motivation, but did not state how it was to be satisfied. Here, as always, the factor of freedom must be recognized in following a motivated path. The stages which make up its journey are, within certain limits, determined by open choices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Thus, the thought of one in many is present in both the proper and the universal name. As Husserl writes: “What is usually designated as `the universality of a word meaning’ is a fact that in no way points to the universality attributed to concepts of kinds as opposed to concepts of individuals. On the contrary, it comprehends both in the same way” (LU, Tüb. ed., II/2, 30; F., p. 692). The distinction between the two is in what constitutes the many. For the proper name, as embodying the thought of an individual, the many refers to individual intuitions; for the generic name, it refers to individual objects. See Ibid., 1I/2, 31–32; F., pp. 693–94. It is to be noted that the meaning signified by the proper name is, in a recognative synthesis, identifiable with the fulfilling sense of the perception of an individual object. As Husserl defines this last: “This is the identical content which, in perception, pertains to the totality of possible perceptual acts which intend the same object, i.e., intend it perceptually as actually the same” (Ibid., 111 1, 51; F., p. 291).

    Google Scholar 

  2. A much more extended accout of this point is made by R. Sokolowski in “Identity in Absence and Presence,” Husserlian Meditations (Evanston, 1974), pp. 18–56.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Thomas Aquinas gives the classical formulation of this distinction in his Quodlibetum, II, 3c; ed. P. Mandonnet (Paris, 1926), p. 43. See also his Le “De Ente et Essentia, Ch. 4; ed. M.D. Rolland-Gosselin (Kain, Belgium, 1926), p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Husserl is not above occasionally contradicting himself. At one point he writes: “The combination a round square really yields a unitary meaning. It is, however, apodictically evident that to this existing meaning no existing object can correspond” (LU, Halle ed., II, 312; see LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 326; F., p. 517). As the context of this passage makes clear, Husserl sees the notion of a round square as inconsistent (widersinnig) but not as grammatically senseless (unsinnig). On a grammatical level of a substantive modified by an adjective, it does have a unity in its sense. Now, to speak of an inconsistent meaning as existing does not just contradict the passage quoted in our text, it also goes against Husserl’s carefully worked out doctrine of the being of the ideal. As we shall see, Husserl will constantly assert that the ideal being of a species is the same as the ideal possibility of its instantiations existing. Thus, without the latter, we cannot speak of ideal being. Here, as always, the Logische Untersuchungen’s individual statements must be weighed in the context of its continuously expressed doctrine.

    Google Scholar 

  5. The distinction between the species as a concept and the species as an object is made in LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 102–103; F., pp. 331–32. See also Ibid., I111, 222; F., p. 431.

    Google Scholar 

  6. In other words, objects are possible that are never actually grasped. See LU, Tüb. ed., II/ 1, 219; F., p. 428.

    Google Scholar 

  7. It is typical of Husserl’s rather troubled relations with Frege that he makes only a general reference to this “Preface.” See LU, Tüb. ed., I, 169, fn. 1;F., p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  8. It is to be noted that this notion becomes fully defined only in the second edition of the Logische Untersuchungen. One may compare, e.g., Husserl’s remarks on LU, Halle ed., II, 21 and his rewriting of these on LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 21; F., p. 265.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The same assertion is made on the level of the predicability of a term. Universal predicability is a function of a term’s specific unity. See LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 148; F., p. 372.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The relation between possibility and unifiability is expressed by Husserl as follows: “In the limiting case of a single content, the validity of a single species may be defined as its unifiability `with itself.’… The difference between speaking of unifiability and possibility lies simply in the fact that while the latter designates the straightforward validity of a species, the former (prior to the widening of the concept to the limiting case) designates the relation of the component species in a species that counts as one” (LU, Tüb. ed., II/2, 106, 107; F., pp. 752, 753).

    Google Scholar 

  11. See also LU, Tüb. ed., II/1, 279; F., pp. 477–78; Ibid., II/1, 283; F., pp. 480–81.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1981 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mensch, J.R. (1981). The Category of the Ideal. In: The Question of Being in Husserl’s Logical Investigations . Phaenomenologica, vol 81. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3446-2_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3446-2_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8264-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3446-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics