Skip to main content

Nonreductivism: The Relevance of N-Continuity

  • Chapter
  • 238 Accesses

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 86))

Abstract

In the previous chapter I have argued that N-continuity is a part of folk-psychology in more respects than that its being a precondition for memory. The concept of N-continuity and its corollary—diachronic mental holism—does not just help to solve problems facing a psychological continuity criterion of personal identity, then, its reality is quite independent of this explanatory function. Now it is time to see whether N-continuity has consequences for the philosophy of mind. In this chapter I claim that it has.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The argument from these sections is taken largely from Slors (1998c).

    Google Scholar 

  2. The fact that no mental state can be cast in terms of its physical realiser does not preclude the possibility that we might be able to infer the existence and nature of a mental state from information concerning the realiser, as some analytical functionalists think is possible. The absence of classical mental-to-physical bridge laws, then, does not imply the absence of nomological relations between physical states and mental states.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Baker (1993) makes a similar point, showing the incompatibility of mental causation with the conjunction of strong supervenience (which is akin to the physical realisation thesis) and the causal closedness of the physical. Her point, unlike Kim’s, is that we should regard this as a reductio ad absurdum of a metaphysics consisting of strong supervenience and the causal closedness of the physical, given the fact that we cannot do without mental causation. Obviously, the untenability of reductivism is a premise of Baker’s.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Roughly speaking there are two types of objection against it. On the one hand, there are objections that claim that Hume did not succeed in establishing a necessary connection between causation and time’s passage. These objections claim that the argument is logically invalid (e.g. Stroud (1977, pp.253–4); Beauchamp and Rosenberg (1981, p.192)). On the other hand, there are objections against the idea of a full analysis of causal asymmetry in terms of time’s passage. Metaphysically minded philosophers tend to look for a more substantial asymmetry between cause and effect than the bare fact that a cause precedes its effect (Papineau (1985)).

    Google Scholar 

  5. It has been shown to be possible, for instance, to interpret the relevant fragment of text as a logically valid argument (Costa (1986)). See for criticism of the metaphysical argument e.g. Ehring (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Note that multiple realisation is not precluded by a nomological characterisation of realisation. It is perfectly possible for one type of mental state to be realisable by various physical state types while each of the realiser state types nomologically implies, under appropriate circumstances, the same mental state type.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Davidson ([19701 1980, pp.215–6): “(...) [I]f anomalous monism is correct, not only can every mental event be uniquely singled out using only physical concepts, but since the number of events that falls under each mental predicate may, for all we know, be finite, there may well exist a physical open sentence coextensive with each mental predicate, though to construct it might involve the tedium of a lengthy uninstructive alternation.”

    Google Scholar 

  8. Davidson (Ibid. P.214): “Anomalous monism resembles materialism in its claim that all events are physical, but it rejects the thesis, usually considered essential to materialism, that mental phenomena can be given a purely physical explanation.”

    Google Scholar 

  9. Kim (1984, 1989, 1993a, 1993b), Honderich (1982), Sosa (1984), Johnston (1985), Fodor (1989), Dretske (1989), and McLaughlin (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Jackson and Pettit (1988, 1990), Pettit (1993a). Kim (1998) takes causal relevance to be more or less identical with what he has labelled ‘supervenient causation’ (Kim 1984). The difference, however, is that in supervenient causation, if a base-level state A causes a base-level state B, all properties that supervene on A appear to superveniently cause all properties that supervene on B. In the case of causal relevance, by contrast, one is able to single out the higher-level properties that are causally relevant from those that aren’t.

    Google Scholar 

  11. I am avoiding the term ‘nomological’ since the connections at issue are at least partly conceptual.

    Google Scholar 

  12. The reasoning behind this is in fact more complex than I make it appear. The point is that since mental states are multiply realisable, mental laws are in fact nomologically heterogeneous. That is, they consist of disjunctions of bits and pieces of various physical laws. This is why even mental regularities can be better explained in physical terms. (See Kim (1997), see for criticism Slors (1997)).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Although one may well argue that even such a thought requires reference to the events of learning the meaning of ‘raining,’ etc. The point is, of course, that such reference can be implicit or abstract for the largest part. However different your experience of learning the meaning of ‘raining’ is from mine, there will be little difference between our respective thoughts with the content ‘it is raining now.’

    Google Scholar 

  14. One thing in Einsteinian physics that might be considered to counter my contention here is the relativity of time indexes of objects, states or events. It should not be thought, however, that this relativity leads to the rejection of the claim that all properties that figure in physical theory can be assigned to objects at one particular time in abstraction from whatever else happens at other times. For it is not the case that an assigned property’s time index requires reference to objects and events at other (relative) times. All the relativity amounts to is that the being co-temporal of property instantiations is dependent upon ones description and frame of reference.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Heisenberg’s uncertainty relation is not a counter-example to this as long as it is given an epistemic reading. That is, as long as it is read as saying that we cannot know the specific time an electron exists when we know the exact place it exists at and vice versa (and not that when an electron exists at a particular place, it does so at no particular time or something along likewise absurd lines), nothing I said is contradicted. Thanks to Florian Bekkers.

    Google Scholar 

  16. I am using the term ‘supervenience’ in the standard analytical sense (there can be no change in the supervening domain unless there is change in the subvening domain), not in Davidson’s slightly idiosyncratic sense.

    Google Scholar 

  17. The terms are taken from Rescher (1996). Apart from the terminology, not much else is taken from it. Rescher, for instance, describes process metaphysics as the view that in physical reality the process has priority over its temporal parts.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Slors, M. (2001). Nonreductivism: The Relevance of N-Continuity. In: The Diachronic Mind. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 86. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3276-5_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3276-5_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5706-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3276-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics