Skip to main content

Abstract

In “Les avatars de l’interprétation de l’Ecriture chez Spinoza”1 Sylvain Zac returns to a question already raised in his book Spinoza et l’interprétation de l’Ecriture: Spinoza’s refutation of the allegorical method of Scriptural interpretation proposed by Maimonides. This refutation is set forth in Chapter XV of the Tractatus Theologico-politicus, which also contains the critique of another allegorical interpretation, that of Rabbi Alpakhar. Dismissing on equal terms those who deny reason any role at all in Scriptural interpretation and those who accord it full authority, Spinoza undertakes to show in this chapter that “theology is not subservient to reason, nor reason to theology.’2 In the preamble to this chapter Spinoza reverts to one of the classic topics in the history of philosophy since the doxographers and, in particular, Sextus Empiricus: the distinction between sceptics and dogmatists. He applies it to the way we conceive the adaptive relationship (accmodari) between reason and theology or, to be more precise, between reason and the meaning of Scripture (sensus Scripturae). Those whom Spinoza qualifies here as sceptics, those who deny the certitude of reason, hold that reason must adapt itself to Scripture, while th ”dogmatics“ maintain that the meaning of Scripture must be accommodated to reason.

This paper was translated from the French by Helen Sebba. with the collaboration of R.H. Popkin. A first copy of this text was first published in French in Nature. croyance, raison, Mélanges offerts à S. Zac. ENS Fontenay, juin 1992.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. This text (written in 1962) constitutes the third essay in Essais spino:istes (Vrin, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  2. TTP, in R.H.M. Elwes (trans.), The Chief Works of Benedict de Spino:a 2 vols. (New York: Dover, 1951), hereafter referred to as “Elwes”, p. 190: Carl Gerhardt, Spino:a Opera 4 vols., (Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1925), Vol. 111, p. 180, hereafter referred to as “Gebhardt”.

    Google Scholar 

  3. In Pvrrhonian Hypotyposes, Vol. I, p. 1, Sextus draws a distinction between the seekers of truth: those who believe they have found it and are called dogmatists (e.g., Aristotle, Epicurus, the Stoics); those who assert that it is impossible to grasp the truth (Clitomachus, Cameades and some other Academicians); and those who persevere in their search: the sceptics.

    Google Scholar 

  4. “Astronomical error” is a free though literal translation of the Spinozist metaphor: “toto coelo errare”.

    Google Scholar 

  5. “Chwr(133)adeo uterque hic scilicet sine ratione, ille vero cum ratione insaniet,” TTP, Elwes, p. 190; Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Common as to genus; different as to species.

    Google Scholar 

  7. “Lac, op. cit. (note I), 29/63.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See, in Chap. VII, the rigorous parallel between the method of interpreting nature and the method of interpreting Scripture; also our study “Les deux livres de la nature et de l’Ecriture”, l’Ecriture Sainte au temps de Spinoza et dons le système Spinoziste, PU Paris Sorbonne, 1992–4, and Chap. XV “Sed tam hos quam illos toto coelo errare er,jam dictis constat” (my italics). Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  9. pinoza, Letter LXIX, in A. Wolf (ed.), The Correspondence of Spinoza (New York: Dial Press, n.d.), pp. 335–36; Gebhardt; Vol. IV, p. 360.

    Google Scholar 

  10. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 36; Elwes, p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Locke, Essay concerning Human Understanding and Leibniz, Nouveaux Essais, IV, Chap. XIX.

    Google Scholar 

  12. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 187: Elwes, p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Although the Religio rationalis is posterior (1676–78) to the TTP, it defends the very same arguments that Spinoza criticizes in Chapter XV.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Jacob Ostens in Spinoza, Letter XLII, Wolf, p. 243, Gebhardt, Vol. IV, p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See, for example, the refutation of Renier de Mansvelt.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Spinoza, Letter XLIII, Wolf, p. 258; Gebhardt, IV, p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  17. An argument which presupposes that a book has no value except in so far as it proclaims truths, that there is no truth over than that of a speculative order, and that God, being the source of all truth and the author of the Bible, necessarily expressed those speculative truths in the Bible but in an implicit form which human reason, as it becomes more knowledgeable and more learned, makes explicit.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Language unworthy of God (as opposed to théoprépös) may mean anthropomorphic language or speaking of God as corporeal.

    Google Scholar 

  19. With the exception of those illuminati who claim that the Bible is wholly inspired, even as to the literality of all these passages, and who are not taken into account here.

    Google Scholar 

  20. This distinction between sceptics and dogmatists also occurs in Meyer, in the preamble to the Interpres, where it is applied to the “theologians of this century.” But with a difference: for Meyer the dogmatists are all the theologians who claim to derive a true and evident knowledge from Holy Scripture but who split into rival sects because they differ as to the content of what they hold to be certain and evident. By sceptics he means the Catholic theologians who affirm that “the truths of religion can only be based plausibly on Holy Scripture” and who therefore submit their theological arguments to the superior judgment of another person. This supreme judge in theological matters means the Pope or the councils, who are themselves drawn from the class of dogmatists.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Spinoza, Cogita metaphvsica, Vol II, p. viii.

    Google Scholar 

  22. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 182; Elwes, p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  23. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 181; Elwes, p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  24. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 187; Elwes, p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Louis Meyer. Philosophia S. Scripturae Interpres (Amsterdam. 1666), Chap. XI, Sec. 9, p. 129; and p. 174 of the French translation, Jacqueline Lagrée and Pierre-Francois Moreau (trans.), La Philosophie interprète de I Ecriture Sainte, (Paris: Intertextes éditeur, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  26. TTP, XV, Gebhardt. Vol. III, p. 181; Elwes, p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  27. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 184; Elwes, p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Notably on the question of providence, the freedom of man and election for eternity, as is shown by the Short Treatise as well as by the dual formulation of certain problems (e.g., the problem of transgression and evil) in the Tractatus Theologico-politicus (ad captum doctorum) and in the Ethics (acaptura sapientiun?) On this point see Jacqueline Laggrée. “Les notions communes religieuses, antécédents et enjeux du credo minimum” in Dio, l’uomo,la lihertà: Studi sul “breve trattato” di Spinoza, a cura di Filippo Mignini, Japadre, L’Aquila-Roma. 1990, p. 457 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  29. “Insinare cum ratione”,TTP, Chap. XV. Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 180: Elwes, p. 190.

    Google Scholar 

  30. “Incerta haec si postules/ratione certa facere, nihilo plus agas/quam si des operam, ut cum ratione insanias.” Terence. The Eunuch, lines 61–63. As Proietti has shown, the TTP is full of crypto-quotations from Terence, particularly from The Eunuch

    Google Scholar 

  31. “Dicentes enim se esse sapientes, stulti facti sunt.” (Rom. 1:22).

    Google Scholar 

  32. “Verbum Dei verbi syngraphum”. TTP, Gebhardt. Ill. p. 182; Elwes, p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  33. TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 185: Elwes, p. 195.

    Google Scholar 

  34. TTP. Gebhardt. Vol. III, p. 187: Elwes. p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Interpres,Epilogue, p. 248 of French translation by Lagrée and Moreau.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. the concluding lines of Chap. XV of the TTP.

    Google Scholar 

  37. “And we shall see the publication of authoritative pages on God. the rational soul, the supreme happiness of man, and the means of attaining eternal life.” Interpres Epilogue. p. 249 in the French translation.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Short Treatise, TTP, Ethics, as well as certain letters.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Scriptural interpretation based on different sorts of reading but also interpretation of individual practices (e.g., those of the prophets or the faithful) or collective practices (e.g., the Hebrew nation’s demand for a king such as other nations had).

    Google Scholar 

  40. “For it is as impossible to dissolve the love which such bear one another, since it is founded on the love which each has for the knowledge of truth, as it is to refuse to embrace the truth once it has been grasped.” Spinoza. Letter XIX, Wolf, p. 146; Gebhardt, Vol. IV, p. 87.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Spinoza, Letter XLIII. Wolf, p. 259; Gebhardt, Vol. IV, p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Spinoza. Letter XLII. Wolf, p. 254: Gebhardt. Vol. IV, p. 218.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See Grotius (Meletius and DGP). Wissowatty (Religio rationalis), D’Huisseau (Réunion du christianisme) and Jacqueline Lagrée. Lu raison ardente, (Paris, Vrin, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  44. “Who, unless he were desperate or mad, would wish to bid an incontinent farewell to reason, or to despise the arts and sciences. or to deny reason’s certitude?” TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III. p. 187: Elwes, p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Given, in fact, in the Ethics. On this point see A. Matheron, Le Christ et le salut des ignorants Che: Spino:a Aubier. Paris 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  46. “Propterea omnibus universalis est.” TTP, Gebhardt, Vol. III, p. 185; Elwes, p. 195.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Zac, op. cit. (note 1), 29/63.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1994 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lagrée, J. (1994). Irrationality with or without Reason. In: Force, J.E., Popkin, R.H. (eds) The Books of Nature and Scripture: Recent Essays on Natural Philosophy, Theology and Biblical Criticism in the Netherlands of Spinoza’s Time and the British Isles of Newton’s Time. International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales D’Histoire des Idées, vol 139. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3249-9_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3249-9_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4321-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3249-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics