Skip to main content

Art and the Reenchantment of Sensuous Human Activity

  • Chapter
The Aesthetics of Enchantment in the Fine Arts

Part of the book series: Analecta Husserliana ((ANHU,volume 65))

  • 229 Accesses

Abstract

Contemporary aestheticians face a question that has troubled writers since the Enlightenment: What is the role of the arts, when scientific rationalism and empirical understanding undermine our belief in the autonomy of each person? One reply consists of two familiar moves: the reiteration of dangerous effects caused by the hegemony of empirical thinking, and the affirmation that artworks serve as instruments for an emancipatory contact with some pre-objective domain. It is our challenging task to find an interpretation that upholds both of these moves, without linking aesthetic practices to the outmoded notion of a human subjectivity that is wholly disembodied, abstract and detached from actual life.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Edmund Husserl, “Philosophy and the Crisis of European Humanity,” in The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, trans. David Carr (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970 ), pp. 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, “The Concept of Enlightenment,” Ecology, ed. Carolyn Merchant (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press International, 1994 ), pp. 44–47.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Michel Foucault, “Two Lectures,” in Critique and Power, Recasting the Foucault/Habermas Debate, ed. Michael Kelly ( Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994 ), pp. 22–23.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, ed. Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedemann, trans. C. Lenhardt (London: Routledge and Keegan Paul, 1984); and Herbert Marcuse, The Aesthetic Dimension ( Boston: Beacon Press, 1978 ).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, ed. Claude Lefort, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968); and “Eye and Mind,” The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader, ed. Galen Johnson, trans. ed. Michael Smith ( Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1993 ).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement (The Hague: Kluwer, 1982), pp. 576–579; Galen Johnson, “Ontology and Painting,” in The Merleau-Ponty Aesthetics Reader (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1993), pp. 37, 47; Judith Butler, Bodies that Matter (New York: Routledge, 1993), p. 69; Patrick Burke, “Listening at the Abyss,” and Monika Langer, “Merleau-Ponty and Deep Ecology,” in Ontology and Alterity in Merleau-Ponty,eds. Galen Johnson and Michael Smith (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1990), pp. 82, 96, 126.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “Eye and Mind,” p. 121.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory,p. 342.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Herbert Marcuse, The Aesthetic Dimension,pp. 6, 7, 37.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Theodor Adorno, The Aesthetic Dimension,pp. 343, 350. In a similar fashion, Clive Bell states that art is an “immediate means to the good” which transports us far from human interests, ideas, facts, and activities, toward peaks of exhalation. See Clive Bell, “The Aesthetic Hypothesis: Significant Form and Aesthetic Emotion,” The Philosophy of the Visual Parts,P. Alperson (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 122–23, 125–26.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Herbert Marcuse, The Aesthetic Dimension,p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., pp. 9, 13.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Theodor Adorno, Aesthetic Theory,pp. 343, 351.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Herbert Marcuse, Aesthetic Dimension,p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Karl Marx, The German Ideology,in Karl Marx Selected Readings,ed. David McLellan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 160. This reading of “praxis” still circulates within some materialist philosophies today, even when empirical discourse is described, more appropriately, as petite and as a means for tactical intervention.

    Google Scholar 

  16. To observe the visible flesh of one’s own body, it is sufficient to look at the duck-rabbit figure, which is often mentioned in philosophical discussions of human perception. The visible aspect of one’s own surroundings persists across the breaks in perception that occur, as one shifts back and forth between consciousness of a duck-shape and the recognition of a rabbit-shape.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible,p. 135.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Karl Marx, “Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts,” in Karl Marx Selected Readings,p. 94. Empirical knowledge is dependent upon sensuous human activity, and sensuous activity marks the human individual’s living contact with nature; hence, science tells us about real, actual people. In such passages, sensuous activity is not yet discussed wholly in terms of the objective knowledge which science offers concerning human conditions.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Iris Young, “Women Recovering Our Clothes,” Throwing Like a Girl and Other Essays in Feminist Philosophy and Social Theory ( Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990 ), p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible,p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See Walter Stace, “The Nature of Mysticism,” in Philosophy of Religion,eds. William Rowe and William Wainwright (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1998), pp. 366–367: the extrovertive mystic is said to advance by means of the senses toward “the apprehension of an ultimate non-sensuous unity in all things.”

    Google Scholar 

  22. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “Eye and Mind, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brubaker, D. (2000). Art and the Reenchantment of Sensuous Human Activity. In: Kronegger, M., Tymieniecka, AT. (eds) The Aesthetics of Enchantment in the Fine Arts. Analecta Husserliana, vol 65. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3234-5_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3234-5_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5405-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3234-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics