Skip to main content

The So-Called Logical Relations

  • Chapter
  • 140 Accesses

Abstract

The relations which Frege would have called Grundsteine of his system (GRG I, p. 3) are examined. Why should such relations be called logical rather than, for instance, ontological (3.1)? “Subject—predicate” in Frege has a different meaning from that of traditional logic (3.3); traditional philosophy has taken into account facts covered by Frege’s UF and UO (3.4). But the most interesting point is what we call hierarchy of predicates, about which our contemporary (Fregean) philosophy of logic has not yet provided a clear statement; traditional logic, to the contrary, was somehow “suffocated” by such a hierarchy of predicates (3.5). Some aspects of the relations between Husserl and Frege are next considered. Husserl’s Philosophie der Arithmetik was still pre-Fregean in matters of predication-theory (3.62), whereas Frege’s review of Husserl’s book was still pre-Aristotelian, since Frege did not realize that there was a hierarchy of predicates behind Husserl’s “psychologism” (3.63).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. The falling of an individual under a concept (UZBG, p. 3).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bartlett [1], p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  3. For the following remarks, cf. 7.54.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Frege speaks of die logischen Beziehungen in UZBG, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  6. We shall abbreviate this by “UO”.

    Google Scholar 

  7. For instance, pp. 3, 5, 8, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  11. (concepts), UZBG, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  12. UZBG, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  13. UZBG, GRG II, §§ 162–164.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. GRL, § 9; tyrannicides are said to be parts of murder as a whole, and Frege comments: “Hier hat man die logische Unterordnung.”

    Google Scholar 

  15. GRL, § 47. The example is “alle Wallfische sind Säugethiere”.

    Google Scholar 

  16. GRG I (p. 24 note) confirms this.

    Google Scholar 

  17. GRL, § 53.

    Google Scholar 

  18. GRL, § 70.

    Google Scholar 

  19. BGGE, p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  20. For example (apart from BGGE, p. 194), WIF, p. 665; HUSS, p. 326. As an example of not distinguishing predication and identity, let us consider the following text (the author would assume that “W. Scott” is predicated about the author of Waverley): “Cum vero in definitione audis, ”de pluribus“ [the author means his definition of nomen universale = quod praedicatur de pluribus],nomine ”Plurium“ intellige plura secundum idem nomen. Nam ut nomen aliquod dicatur commune non satis est si praedicetur de iis, quae dicuntur plura secundum aliud nomen, sic nomina singularia, communia esse iudicabuntur. Platonis siquidem nomen una sola ratione acceptum, praedicatur de pluribus attributis Platonis, ut pote de hoc Aristonis filio, de hoc Philosopho, de hoc Aristotelis praeceptore. Nomen etiam Conimbricae praedicatur de pluribus attributis Conimbricae, ut de urbe prope Mondam sita, de hac bonarum artium cultrice ...” (Fonseca [1], Lib. Primus, Cap. XXVI).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Bartlett [1], p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  22. BGGE, p. 201; cf. UGG1, p. 373.

    Google Scholar 

  23. GRG I, p. 240.

    Google Scholar 

  24. GRG I, § 34.

    Google Scholar 

  25. KSCH, p. 442.

    Google Scholar 

  26. UBR, p. 9; UGG2(III), p. 427 note. In the “inedita” we have “Subordination” for “Unterordnung”.

    Google Scholar 

  27. This is an interpretation which seems correct, although the difficulties implied by the ontological square should be considered. It would be enough to recall Frege’s philosophy of number: numbers concern concepts because they say how many individuals fall under each concept.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf., for instance, GRL, § 54.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. Section 6.71.

    Google Scholar 

  30. GRL associates Begriff and mögliches Prädikat (§ 66 note), or just Prädikat (§ 77). This Kantian terminology also occurs in GRG II (§ 56). In BGGE “predicate” or “predicative” are used to characterize unsaturatedness which indicates the extreme importance those terms have in Frege’s system (BGGE, p. 197, note). WIF mentions in several places subjects of predication (for example, p. 658). The following text (from a later paper) shows how Frege understands the relation subject-predicate in a sentence: “Nehmen wir den Satz ‘Zwei ist eine Primzahl’. Wir unterscheiden hier sprachlich ein Subjekt “Zwei” und einen prädikativen Bestandteil ”ist eine Primzahl”” (UGGI, p. 371).

    Google Scholar 

  31. For example SUB, p. 35 (first line).

    Google Scholar 

  32. For example UGG2(I), p. 305, bottom; BGGE, p. 193, note.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. 6.7.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cf. Section 6.8.

    Google Scholar 

  35. In “Blut ist rot” the subject is “Blut”, Sigwart [1], I, p. 117. In “l’homme est un animal”, “l’homme” is the subject, “animal” the predicate, Gardeil [1], p. 51, 90. Cf. also Quine [1], § 14 and § 23. Also Geach [2].

    Google Scholar 

  36. BGGE, p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Schröder’s curious idea (certainly not only his) was that “einige Menschen” denotes a class, but a class consisting of an undetermined number of individuals (KSCH, p. 435, 441 note).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. Geach [2]. Aristotle views “every” as giving to the sentence a universal character (Aristotle [1], Perihermeneias, 7, 17b, 12 ).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Indefinita est quae habet subiectum universale sine ulla nota, ut homo est iustus“ (Pacius [2], cap. 5, n. 6). Frege has been interested in the vestiges.of ”propositiones indefinitae“, such as ”das Pferd ist ein vierbeiniges Thier“ (UWB, BGGE, p. 196). He interprets this as a universal affirmative sentence. Leaving aside whether this interpretation is absolutely valid, let us only refer for this use of the definite article as a universal quantifier, to Sigwart [1] (p. 117) and Reichenbach [2] (p. 25).

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. Chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  41. GRL, p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  42. This will be confirmed by the inedita (letter to Husserl, Oct. 30, 1906).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Petrus Hispanus [1] (2.09) defines: “Individuum est quod de uno solo praedicatur, ut Socrates et Plato”, where one would think rather of individual concepts or idées individuelles (Port-Royal [1], I, Ch. VI) than of individuals proper. Incidentally, Carnap’s proposal of speaking of individual concepts (Carnap [1], § 9, p. 41 top) is indeed quite in agreement with the traditional approach. Perhaps Kant’s term “Anschauung” reflects the traditional ambiguity of “individuum”: (1) without intuitions, concepts are empty, where “intuition” means existent individual, (2) the intuitions “apply” to only one object, while concepts apply to many objects, where “intuition” means individual concept (cf. Eisler [1], “Anschauung”). Frege noticed, in GRL, § 12, an ambiguity in Kant’s “Anschauung”, which seems to be related to this one. An extensive discussion is to be found in Caietanus [2], p. 62f.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ultimate subject.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Praedicatio enim est quiddam quod completur per actionem intellectus componentis et dividentis, habens fundamentum in re ipsa unitatem eorum quorum unum de altero dicitur“ (Aquinas [3], Chap. III). Cf. Ioannes a Sto Thoma [1], p. 470a, top. Frege, on the contrary, says: ”Bemerkt sei hierzu noch, daß das gesperrt gedruckte ist sowie sind als bloße Copula aufzufassen ist, ohne irgend einen besonderen Inhalt, dass also damit keine Identität gemeint ist“ (KSCH, p. 442).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Cf. Chapter 1.

    Google Scholar 

  47. This is actually Porphyry’s evasive procedure, to consider only the “substantial” tree, cf. Section 1.41.

    Google Scholar 

  48. As for the species infima the natural question is why there should be at all such a limit in approaching individuals through Unterordnung structures. The answer seems to depend on the notion of matter; male and female do not make a new species because they are properties deriving from matter (Aristotle [2], I, 9).

    Google Scholar 

  49. Porphyry [1], (Isagoge),pp. 6, 12–13.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Now it is clear that if the predications terminate in both the upward and the downward direction (by “upward” I mean the ascent to the more universal, by “downward” the descent to the more particular), the middle terms cannot be infinite in number“ (Aristotle [3.1], Anal. Post., A20).

    Google Scholar 

  51. Aristotle says that a predicate (5tp.oi a thing (Aristotle [1], 2b, 31). Some humanist commentators have translated this Greek word by declarare (Pacius [1], Gruchius [1]).

    Google Scholar 

  52. Aristotle [2], B2, 996b, 15f.

    Google Scholar 

  53. This concept is important in Frege’s foundation of arithmetic.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Aristotle [3], An. Post., B, 10, 94a, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Aristotle [2], A, 17, 1022a, 8–10.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Locke [1], III, 6, § 2; also § 5.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Aquinas [1], 1048. Cf. Porphyry [1], for the notion of differentia.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Martinus de Dacia [1], n. 34; Husserl [5], § 90.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Duns Scotus on Boethius: “Secundo modo accipit Boethius, distinguendo rem contra modum rei, sicut loquitur libro de Trinitate. ”Patet“, inquit, ”quae sit differentia praedicationum, quia aliae quidem rem mostrant, aliae quidem quasi circumstantiam rei; quia istae praedicantur sic quod secundum se rem aliquam mostrant. Illae vero ut non esse, sed potius extrinsecus aliquid apponunt“. Vult ergo distinguere rem contra circumstantiam; et sic, secundum eum, sola tria genera (substantia, qualitas et quantitas) rem mostrant; alia vero rei circumstantias.” (In Fernandez-Garcia [1], distinctio ens-res.)

    Google Scholar 

  60. A Renaissance author (Eust. a Sto. Paulo) shows how the passage from “accident” to “mode” was accomplished: “Quarta conclusio. Essentia accidentis modus quidam est substantiae; omne enim accidens substantiam aliqua ratione modificat” (in Gilson [3], p. 104, “essence”).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Port-Royal [1], I, Ch. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Kant [4], 2. Abs., p. 242. Vaihinger [l] (I, p. 264) clearly explains how reine Anschauung is introduced in the sophisticated traditional theory of predication. Locke [1] (II, 31, § 6) had already made it clear that nothing “flows” from the (nominal) essence. Kant nevertheless has to explain the fact of synthetical a priori knowledge.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Cf. Kauffmann [1], p. 335. Of course, this is but an example of “negative theology”.

    Google Scholar 

  64. P. 76 bottom.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Carnap [1], § 27. Cf. also Anscombe-Geach [1], p. 34; Quine [3], p. 155. An interesting comparison of both approaches (i.e., with and without hierarchy of predicates) is in Springer [1].

    Google Scholar 

  66. Husserl [4]. For Frege-Husserl in general, cf. Fr llesdal [1].

    Google Scholar 

  67. HUSS.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Husserl [4], pp. 11, 91, 92.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Frege in GRL, § 24, Husserl in [4], p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Javellus [1] (f. 164) reduces number to a particular category of being (quantitas).

    Google Scholar 

  71. Husserl [4], Chapter IV in fine.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Frege mentions only once, briefly and incidentally, Husserl’s view of the universality of number (HUSS, p. 315).

    Google Scholar 

  73. Which Frege thus easily accuses of psychologism (not using this term). But if Husserl employs a “psychological” terminology, this is motivated by his program of ensuring and respecting the “transcendental” (in the scholastic sense) nature of number and other formal ontological categories (cf. Husserl [4], pp. 86, 91). As we shall see shortly (Section 3.63), Husserl’s program plus his traditional approach to the hierarchy of predicates determined that apparent psychologism. (For Frege and psychologism, see Papst [1].)

    Google Scholar 

  74. Multitude, plurality.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Husserl [4], p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  76. For the use of this adjective “concrete”, see Husserl [4], pp. 10, 67, 89, 185 (bottom), etc.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See below.

    Google Scholar 

  78. The example is given in Husserl [4], p. 79; it is also mentioned by Frege in HUSS, pp. 322–323.

    Google Scholar 

  79. For example Husserl [4], pp. 87, 88, 164, etc.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid., pp. 87, 185.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Die Zahl ist die allgemeine Vielheitsform unter welcher der Inbegriff der Gegenstände a, b, c fällt“ (Husserl [4], p. 185). If ”allgemeine Vielheitsform“ = ”abstracte Vielheit“, we may conclude that {der Mond, die Röte, Napoleon} falls under {Etwas, Etwas, Etwas}. But there is a more explicit text: ”Zwei Äpfel, zwei Menschen, ein Apfel und ein Mensch, u.s.w. sind sämmtlich zwei, weil sie concrete Inbegriffe repräsentieren, welche durch das Zählungsverfahren gerade unter die abstracte Mengenform: Eins und Eins, fallen und unter keine andere“ (Husserl [4], p. 162).

    Google Scholar 

  82. Unless it is explicitly agreed that the concept of Vielheit is itself a Vielheit, as the concept of entity is an entity. But for Husserl the concept Vielheit is higher than the abstracte Vielheiten; see below.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Husserl [4], pp. 90, 158.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Cf. the next note. Also, Husserl [4], p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Bei dem Namen Anzahl compliciert sich die Sache noch dadurch, daß er nicht bloß als allgemeiner Name für irgend welche concrete Mengen, sondern auch als allgemeiner Name für jede unter den Begriff der Anzahl fallenden besonderen Zahlen: Zwei, Drei, Vier… dient“ (Husserl [4], p. 154).

    Google Scholar 

  86. In this text I assume that “allgemeiner Name für irgend welche concrete Mengen [zu sein]” means that these Mengen fall under the concept denoted by that general name. There is justification for this in Husserl himself, some pages previous: “Jeder abstracte Name wird in einer zweifachen Bedeutung gebraucht; das eine Mal dient er als Name für den abstracten Begriff als solchen, das andere Mal als Name für irgend eine unter diesen Begriff fallenden Gegenstand” (Husserl [4], p. 151).

    Google Scholar 

  87. The fact that both concrete Vielheiten and abstracte Vielheiten (i.e. numbers) fall under the Anzahlbegriff had already been suggested by Husserl at the beginning of the book: “Der Anzahlbegriff umfaßt also, obschon erst auf dem Wege über die Umfänge seiner Speciesbegriffe, der Zahlen Zwei, Drei, Vier,... dieselben concreten Phänomene wie der Begriff der Vielheit” (Husserl [4], p. 9). Cf. also the example given by Husserl on page 189.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Cf. Husserl’s text quoted at the end of the preceding note; also Husserl [4], p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  89. HUSS, p. 313.

    Google Scholar 

  90. HUSS, p. 313.

    Google Scholar 

  91. HUSS, p. 324.

    Google Scholar 

  92. HUSS, p. 326. As if “man” were a name of Hans as “Hans” is. Cf. Husserl’s semantics of general terms (at the time of Husserl [4]) in note 85 above. Cf. also Section 2. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  93. HUSS, p. 327.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Cf. Chapter 10.

    Google Scholar 

  95. HUSS, p. 326.

    Google Scholar 

  96. With respect to five concrete stones or five concrete syllogistic modes.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Husserl [4], p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Ibid., p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ibid. But of course this is trivially rejected; an apostle is not twelve (p. 181, below).

    Google Scholar 

  100. Ibid., p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Eine leichte Unterscheidung wird zeigen, daß in gewissem Sinne beide Parteien Recht haben. Rechnen wir zum Inhalte einer Vorstellung nur Theilvorstellungen im eigentlichen und strengen Sinne (“innere Merkmale” nannten sie manche Logiker) und betrachten demgemäß Vorstellungen nur dann als vergleichbar, wenn sie gemeinsame Theilinhalte dieser Art besitzen, dann giebt es unendlich viele disparate und unvergleichbare Vorstellungen, und es ist klar, daß dann die Zählung Vergleichbarkeit (in dieser Bedeutung) nicht verlangt, da vielmehr ganz disparate Dinge zusammengezählt werden können. Meine Seele und ein Dreieck sind zwei, obgleich sie keinerlei gemeinsame innere Merkmale besitzen. Rechnen wir jedoch zum Inhalte einer Vorstellung auch alle ihr zukommenden negativen und relativen Bestimmungen (die “äußeren Merkmale”), dann giebt es überhaupt keine unvergleichbaren Vorstellungen; denn es giebt keine, die nicht mindestens als unter den Begriff Etwas fallende, gleichartig sind. Und gerade diese Subsumption unter den Begriff Etwas müssen wir (nach unserer Theorie) hinsichtlich eines jeden der zu zählenden Gegenstände vollziehen, um die Zahl zu erfassen. Insofern ist also richtig, daß die zu zählenden Dinge unter einen gemeinsamen Gattungsbegriff (dies Wort freilich im äußerlichsten Sinne genommen) gebracht werden müssen“ (Husserl [4], p. 158).

    Google Scholar 

  102. Man kann in jedem Falle die gezählten Objecte durch gemeinsame Merkmale (seien es innere oder relative) so genau determinieren, daß der entstehende Gattungsbegriff nur auf die hic et nunc gezählten Objecte päßt und auf keine anderen“ (Husserl [4], pp. 187–188). In the following text we notice some irony with respect to considering as concepts predicates which normally would not be so regarded: ”Urtheilen wir z.B.: der Wagen des Kaisers wird von vier Pferden gezogen, dann würde der Begriff Pferd dieser Anforderung nicht genügen, denn es giebt auch sonst noch Pferde. Anders wenn wir den Begriff “Pferd, das den Wagen des Kaisers zieht”, wählen, insbesondere wenn wir Ort, Raum, Datum und Tageszeit zu notiren nicht vergessen; dieser Begriff päßt nur auf die vier hier concret gegebenen und gezählten Pferde“ (Husserl [4], p. 188).

    Google Scholar 

  103. Die vollste Bestätigung für unsere Auffassung bietet wieder die innere Erfahrung. Fragen wir, worin die Verbindung bestehe, wenn wir z.B. eine Mehrheit so disparater Dinge wie die Röte, Napoleon und der Mond denken, so erhalten wir die Antwort, sie bestehe bloß darin, daß wir diese Inhalte zusammen denken, in einem Akte denken“ (Husserl [4], p. 79).

    Google Scholar 

  104. HUSS, p. 322–323.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Husserl [4], p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Signoriello [1].

    Google Scholar 

  107. I think that such is the correct interpretation of the following text: “Aber nehmen wir selbst an, es wäre immer so, wie man behauptet, wir colligierten und zählten stets nur Objecte, sofern sie unter einen gemeinsamen Begriff fallen, dann geht aus unserer Betrachtung klar hervor, daß die Zahl in keiner Weise als Bestimmung dieses Begriffes angesehen werden kann” (Husserl [4], p. 185). Perhaps because of this (typically traditional) difficulty of viewing higher predicates (i.e., there are already “higher” predicates: animal with respect to man!), Husserl finally arrives at the following formulation: “Nur indirect kann man allenfalls sagen, der Begriff hat die Eigenschaft, daß seinem Umfange die Zahl vier zukommt” (Husserl [4], p. 189).

    Google Scholar 

  108. Cf. Section 5.32.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1967 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Angelelli, I. (1967). The So-Called Logical Relations. In: Studies on Gottlob Frege and Traditional Philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3175-1_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3175-1_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8326-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-3175-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics