Advertisement

Assessment and Discovery in the Limit of Scientific Inquiry

  • Vincent F. Hendricks
  • Stig Andur Pedersen
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 320)

Abstract

Acquisition of knowledge may come about in different ways. One step on the way to acquire knowledge would be to formulate a hypothesis and then evaluate the particular hypothesis in light of incoming evidence. Inductive logics, confirmation theory, and Popper’s deductivist epistemology all adopt this approach. Indeed, proponents of this “generate and test” epistemology have insisted that the core of scientific method is exhausted by the study of methods of hypothesis assessment. This lead Reichenbach to formulate the classical distinction between the context of justification and the context of discovery. Hempel later spoke of a logic of justification but only of a context of discovery just to emphasize the discrepancy. Whether a hypothesis is verified or refuted by the evidence is strictly a logical matter which can be settled “out of court” in a logical or approximately logical fashion. However, it seems to be the case of many, at least early, confirmation theorists or justificationists, like Hempel, that they did not insist on convergence to a correct hypothesis. For them, confirmation was to be an end in itself. In consequence, one could confirm forever heading nowhere near the correct answer.

Keywords

Assessment Method Discovery Method Modus Ponens Empirical Adequacy Knowledge Type 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Gold, E. M. (1967). Language identification in the limit. Information and Control, 10: 447–474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Gutting, G. (1980). The logic of invention and scientific discovery. In Nickles, T. D., editor, Logic and Rationality, pp. 221–234. Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  3. Hendricks, V. F. (1997). Epistemology, Methodology and Reliability. Doc- toral Thesis, Department of Philosophy, University of Copenhagen.Google Scholar
  4. Hendricks, V. F. (2001). The Convergence of Scientific Knowledge. A View from the Limit, Studia Logica Library Trends in Logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  5. Hendricks, V. F. and Pedersen, S. A. (2003). Operators in Philosophy of Science. In preparation.Google Scholar
  6. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief. Cornell University Press, Cornell.Google Scholar
  7. Kelly, K. (1994). Reliable methods. Logic, Methodology and the Philosophy of Science, IX: 353–381.Google Scholar
  8. Kelly, K. (1996). The Logic of Reliable Inquiry. Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  9. Martin, E. and Osherson, D. (1998). Elements of Scientific Inquiry. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  10. Osherson, D., Stob, M., and Weinstein, S. (1986). Systems That Learn. MIT Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  11. Peirce, C. S. (1958). Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings. Wiener, P., editor. Dover Publications, New York.Google Scholar
  12. Poole, D. (1988). A logical framework for default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 36: 27–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Ramsey, F. P. (1931). Knowledge. In Braithwaite, R. B., editor, The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Essays. Harcourt Brace, New York.Google Scholar
  14. Schulte, O. (1996). Hard Choices in Scientific Inquiry. Doctoral Thesis, Department of Philosophy, Carnegie Mellon University.Google Scholar
  15. Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The Scientific Image. Clarendon Press, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2003

Authors and Affiliations

  • Vincent F. Hendricks
    • 1
  • Stig Andur Pedersen
    • 1
  1. 1.Roskilde UniversityDenmark

Personalised recommendations