Skip to main content

Do Genes Code for Traits?

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 320))

Abstract

The orthodox view in evolutionary biology is that genes code for phenotypic traits. Thus an organism’s genotype is standardly characterised as coding for that organism’s phenotype. A code is a species of representation; so, on the received view, genes can be said to represent traits, and genotypes to represent phenotypes. This theory of genetic activity does not imply that genes somehow act alone to produce phenotypic traits. Every biologist knows that development is a complex and distributed process, involving a vast array of causal factors, many of which are located in the wider metabolic and environmental contexts within which genes make their contributions (much more on this below). However, two crucial features of the standard approach in biology are (i) that genes are understood as doing something special in development, and (ii) that the concept of coding helps us to understand what that “something special” is. Thus any adequate account of genetic coding must have the consequence that, of the many causal factors which combine causally during development to produce a fully grown organism, it is the genetic factors alone which end up counting as being representational in character.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Clark, A. and Wheeler, M. (1998). Bringing representation back to life. In Pfeifer, R., Blumberg, B., Meyer, J.-A., and Wilson, S. W., editors, From Animals to Animats 5: the Fifth International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior, pp. 3–12. MIT Press/Bradford Books, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. (1968). The origin of the genetic code. Journal of Molecular Biology, 38: 367–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeLisi, C. (1988). The human genome project. American Scientist, 76: 488–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2000). On the theoretical role of genetic coding. Philosophy of Science, 67: 26–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, B. (1994). How the Leopard Changed its Spots: the Evolution of Complexity. Phoenix, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. and Gray, R. D. (1994). Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 91 (6): 277–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. and Knight, R. D. (1998). What is the developmentalist

    Google Scholar 

  • challenge? Philosophy of Science,65:253–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. (1983). The organism as the subject and object of evolution. Scientia, 118: 63–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, K. (1965). Evolution and the Modification of Behaviour. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. and Varela, F. J. (1987). The Tree of Knowledge: the Bio-logical Roots of Human Understanding. New Science Library, Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J. (1998). Shaping Life: Genes, Embryos and Evolution. Weidenfeld and Nicolson, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J. (1999). The concept of information in biology. Lecture given at the 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Cracow, Poland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oyama, S. (1985). The Ontogeny of Information. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1995). Understanding life: recent work in philosophy of biology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46: 155–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. and Kitcher, P. (1988). The return of the gene. Journal of Philosophy, 85(7):339–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., and Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2001). Two threats to representation. Synthese, 129: 211–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. and Clark, A. (1999). Genic representation: reconciling content and causal complexity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(1):103–135.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wheeler, M. (2003). Do Genes Code for Traits?. In: Rojszczak, A., Cachro, J., Kurczewski, G. (eds) Philosophical Dimensions of Logic and Science. Synthese Library, vol 320. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2612-2_12

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2612-2_12

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6432-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2612-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics