Skip to main content

We Sensualists

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 204))

Abstract

“Today all of us are sensualists,” Nietzsche writes in Book Five of The Gay Science.1 This striking assertion provides a signal for a set of problems concerning knowledge or, more particularly, the relation between knowledge and life. Nietzsche had been concerned with these questions for a long time, but only after Thus Spake Zarathustra did he define them in the ways that provide the theme of this discussion. As his thinking found its own path more and more, Nietzsche moved decisively away from the pessimism and romanticism which had earlier influenced him, and gained a new appreciation of the philosophers of the French Enlightenment, even describing their sensualism and hedonism as the “best inheritance” available to his own century.2 Hence, for example, his suggestion that the credit for Stendhal, in his opinion the greatest French writer of the nineteenth century, must go to “the best, most rigorous philosophical school in Europe, that of Condillac and Destutt de Tracy.”3 The term “sensualist,” as used here, refers in the first instance to these thinkers who, proceeding from the empiricism of Locke, attempted to derive all ideas from elementary sensations. (Hence the alternative expression, “sensationalism.”) It does not imply a preoccupation with sensual pleasure, although the English word may be used most often in that sense.4 On the other hand, it can hardly be denied that any moral philosophy which finds its basic evidence in sensation will be naturally inclined towards hedonism, or at least utilitarianism. Less evident, but equally seen in these French writers, is the affinity between sensualism and a materialist interpretation of human nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. GS 372. Apart from published works of Nietzsche, including the notes included in The Will to Power,all remaining translations are my own, unless otherwise stated.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Nietzsche, Kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke [hereafter: KGW], ed. G. Colli and M. Montinari Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1973-), VII/2, 234.

    Google Scholar 

  3. KGW VIII/3, 455.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Not trusting his readers on this point, Kaufmann translates Sensualisten as “believers in the senses,” a rather misleading phrase in view of the qualification Nietzsche goes on to make in this passage.

    Google Scholar 

  5. KGW II1/3, 207.

    Google Scholar 

  6. GS 373.

    Google Scholar 

  7. KGW VII/2, 264.

    Google Scholar 

  8. BGE, 12. One may here recall the admiring words of Galileo when referring to the heliocentric theories of Aristarchus and Copernicus: “Nor can I ever sufficiently admire the outstanding acumen of those who have taken hold of this opinion and accepted it as true; they have through sheer force of intellect done such violence to their senses as to prefer what reason told them over that which sensible experience plainly showed them to the contrary.” Dialogues Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, trans. Stillman Drake, 2nd ed. ( Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1967 ), 328.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Daybreak,168. See also KGW VII/3, 278 (WP 443).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Nietzsche, Historische-Kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke, Band 4, ed. H.J. Mette and K. Schlechta ( München: C.H. Beck’ sche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1937 ), 84.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See G.J. Stack, “Nietzsche and Lange,” The Modern Schoolman 57 (1980), 137–49, Jörg Salaquarda, “Nietzsche und Lange,” Nietzsche-Studien 7 (1978), 236–53 and G.J. Stack, Lange and Nietzsche (Berlin-New York: de Gruyter, 1983 ).

    Google Scholar 

  12. F.A. Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart ( Iserlohn: Verlag von J. Baedecker, 1866 ), 345.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See e.g. Geschichte des Materialismus,405, for this phrase which is often used by Nietzsche: BGE, 21; also KGW VII/3, 224 and 288 (WP 618), KGW VII/3, 439 and KGW VIII/1, 90 and 110 (WP 622).

    Google Scholar 

  14. BGE, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Geschichte des Materialismus,500.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid.,485.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid.,496.

    Google Scholar 

  18. BGE, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  19. BGE, 15. See also KGW VII/1, 88 and 230.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Twilight of the Idols,“`Reason’ in Philosophy,” sect. 3. Similarly, Zarathustra says, “You should think your own senses through to the end.” Thus Spake Zarathustra,“Upon the Blessed Isles.” Cf. KGW VII/2, 124 (WP 1046).

    Google Scholar 

  21. GS, 112.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Twilight of the Idols, “‘Reason’ in Philosophy,” sect. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  23. KGW V/2, 422.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Heidegger, Nietzsche (Pfullingen: Neske, 1961), Band 1, 375.

    Google Scholar 

  25. On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,2 (in the translation of Peter Preuss). A somewhat similar passage occurs in the book which was the occasion of Nietzsche’s first “untimely meditation,” David Friedrich Strauss’s Der alte and der neue Glaube. Strauss writes: “When the great year of the world has thus elapsed, the formation of a new world begins, in which — according to the Stoic fancy — the earlier one repeats itself precisely, down to particular events and persons (Socrates and Xanthippe).” Der alte and der neue Glaube (Leipzig: Verlag von S. Hirzel, 1872), 155.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Robin Small, “Incommensurability and Recurrence: from Oresme to Simmel,” Journal of the History of Ideas 52 (1991): 121–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. For “constellation” see KGW VII1/3, 68 and 165 (WP 551 and 636); and for “smallest detail,” KGW V/2, 421.

    Google Scholar 

  28. KGW V/2, 421.

    Google Scholar 

  29. KGW VIII/1, 244 (WP 565).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Nietzsche, Gesammelte Werke,Band 4, ed. M. Oehler and R. Oehler (München: Musarion Verlag), 334.

    Google Scholar 

  31. KGW VIII/1, 201 (WP 563).

    Google Scholar 

  32. KGW VIII/1, 244 (WP 565).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Critique of Pure Reason,A162 = B203 and A168 = B210.

    Google Scholar 

  34. The proposition that intensive magnitudes cannot be added together has been put to ingenious use by C.S. Lewis. He begins by observing that if two people are each suffering a toothache of intensity x, it does not follow that anyone is suffering a toothache of intensity 2x. He goes on: “There is no such thing as a sum of suffering, for no one suffers it. When we have reached the maximum that a single person can suffer, we have, no doubt, reached something very horrible, but we have reached all the suffering there can ever be in the universe. The addition of a million fellow-sufferers adds no more pain.” The Problem of Pain (London: Geoffrey Bles, 1940), 103–04. A reply is that sensations have not only intensive but also extensive magnitude, in the multiplicity of subjects who experience them and, within a single person, in their bodily extent and temporal duration. Accordingly, we can say that there is more or less pain in so far as any of these magnitudes increases or decreases. Someone who overlooks that consideration might attempt to prove that eternal punishment is no more severe than the most brief or even momentary punishment, since the intensities of the successive states of pain cannot be added together. Anyone arguing in that way, though, would be forced to concede that eternal bliss is no more rewarding than a very fleeting pleasure.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Critique of Pure Reason,B207.

    Google Scholar 

  36. The pioneers in this area were E.H. Weber and G.T. Fechner, who developed a model for estimating the intensities of sensations, and on that basis postulated a formula in which the magnitudes of sensation and stimulus are related in a logarithmic function.

    Google Scholar 

  37. He goes on: “It is the same with morality. Here accompanying feelings of beneficence or utility arise in someone who perceives a human characteristic in a certain quantum; doubled or tripled, he is afraid of it…” KGW VII/2, 238.

    Google Scholar 

  38. KGW VII/2, 234; reading die `Sinn’ for das ‘Sein,’ as indicated by KGW VII/4/2, 654.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Human, All-too-Human, i 483.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Paul Rée, Der Ursprung der moralischen Empfindungen ( Chemnitz: Verlag von Ernst Schmeitzner, 1877 ).

    Google Scholar 

  41. KGW VIII/l, 244 (WP 565).

    Google Scholar 

  42. KGW VII/2, 183.

    Google Scholar 

  43. For an outline of Dumont’s life and work, see Alexander Buechner, Un philosophe amateur. Essai biographique sur Léon Dumont (1837–1877) avec des extraits de sa correspondance ( Paris: Librairie Félix Alcan, 1884 ).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Léon Dumont, Vergnügen and Schmerz. Zur Lehre den Gefühlen (Leipzig: F.A. Brockhaus, 1876). This volume is a translation of Théorie scientifique de la sensibilité. Le plaisir et la peine ( Paris: Librairie Germer Baillière, 1875 ).

    Google Scholar 

  45. The term “science” may suggest consistency with a reductionist and materialist program in psychology, hut does not imply a reliance on empirical evidence; indeed, Dumont argues that a science of pleasure and pain is like dynamics or mathematics, in being concerned not with facts, but with more general and abstract objects. Vergnügen and Schmerz,100.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Vergnügen and Schmerz,98.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid.,307.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid.,82.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid.,129.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid.,136. An equally surprising result of his theory emerges when the principle of the conservation of energy is taken into account. This law implies that any increase of energy in one location must correspond to a decrease of energy elsewhere. According to Dumont’s theory, these processes are identical with pleasure and pain respectively. Hence, the amount of pleasure in the world must always be exactly equal to the amount of pain. This invalidates any claim that existence as a whole contains more pain than pleasure, or vice versa — in other words, it disposes of both pessimism and optimism, so understood. It has an even more startling implication: that for every subject experiencing pleasure, another must experience pain. Dumont acknowledges this only by referring to the successes of the human race at the expense of other species in the struggle for existence. He forbears to mention that a similar conclusion must also apply to individuals. Accordingly, he does not address the novel ethical problems that would arise from an assumption that one person’s pleasure necessitates another’s pain.

    Google Scholar 

  51. KGW VII/1, 308 and 322.

    Google Scholar 

  52. BGE 225. See also KGW VIII/1, 338; VIII/2, 272 and 275; VIIU3, 127 and 152 (WP 579, 701, 669, 478 and 702).

    Google Scholar 

  53. KGW VIIU3, 127 (WP 478).

    Google Scholar 

  54. KGW VII1/3, 92 (WP 688).

    Google Scholar 

  55. KGW VIII/3, 150 (WP 699).

    Google Scholar 

  56. BGE 13.

    Google Scholar 

  57. GS 127.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Vergnügen and Schmerz, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  59. See KGW VII/1, 322.

    Google Scholar 

  60. KGW VIIU3, 150 (WP 699).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Twilight of the Idols,“Maxims and Arrows,” sect. 12. It is only fair to point out that this is not how Englishmen see themselves. As A.P. Herbert puts it, “The Englishman never enjoys himself except for a noble purpose.” Uncommon Law (London: Eyre Methuen, 1977), 198.

    Google Scholar 

  62. KGW VIII/3, 70 (WP 695).

    Google Scholar 

  63. KGW VIIU2, 33 (WP 516).

    Google Scholar 

  64. KGW VIII/1, 200 (WP 1045).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Small, R. (1999). We Sensualists. In: Babich, B.E. (eds) Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 204. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2428-9_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2428-9_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5234-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2428-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics