Skip to main content

Freedom and Blameworthiness

  • Chapter
Moral Responsibility and Ontology

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 7))

Abstract

In this contribution I will argue that the intelligibility of the category of actions that I call ‘exemplary blameworthy’ depends upon the existence of robust alternative possibilities. This necessity of alternative possibilities is no problem for those who accept a conditional or hypothetical analysis of ‘could have done otherwise,’ although these views have notorious problems of their own. It is a problem, though, for those who want to accept Frankfurt’s famous counter-examples to the principle of alternative possibilities or for those who want to establish compatibilism along the lines suggested by these counter-examples. It is this kind of compatibilism that is the focus of this contribution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Deep responsibility’ is distinguished from ‘superficial responsibility.’ The latter refers to our ‘merely causal’ responsibility for events; i.e. the kind of responsibility we share with natural phenomena, animals and artefacts.

    Google Scholar 

  2. P. Van Inwagen, An Essay on Free Will ( Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983 ), 16.

    Google Scholar 

  3. T. Honderich, How Free are You? The Determinism Problem ( Oxford: Oxford UP, 1993 ), 138.

    Google Scholar 

  4. H. G. Frankfurt, ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, The importance of what we care about ( Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1988 ), 11 – 25.

    Google Scholar 

  5. R. J. Wallace, Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments ( Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1994 ).

    Google Scholar 

  6. S. Wolf, Freedom within Reason ( Oxford: Oxford UP, 1990 ).

    Google Scholar 

  7. The hierarchical model was, at the same time, also developed by Gerald Dworkin, but is primarily known through the work of Frankfurt. G. Dworkin, The theory and practice of autonomy ( Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1988 ).

    Google Scholar 

  8. H. G. Frankfurt, ‘Identification and Wholeheartedness’, The importance of what we care about,159–176.

    Google Scholar 

  9. H. G. Frankfurt, ‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’, The importance of what we care about,1–10; H. G. Frankfurt, ‘Coercion and Moral Responsibility’,op. cit., 26–46.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Wolf s view and Wallace’s view differ greatly in this as in other respects. Wallace restricts the exonerating or exempting circumstances to those that invalidate the powers of reflective self-control itself, whereas Wolf contends that the mitigating or exonerating circumstances include those in which we ‘lack the opportunity to exercise the abilities relevant to responsibility.’ S. Wolf, op. cit., 101–102; R. J. Wallace, op. cit., 187–188, 223 – 225.

    Google Scholar 

  11. It also, thirdly, suggests a way to understand the kind of Compatibilism discussed in this contribution, as a third option distinct from both traditional Incompatibilism and traditional Compatibilism. I elaborate on this in the extended version of this contribution.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Benson who suggests that the grammar of freedom is perhaps ‘relational.’ P. Benson, ‘Freedom and Value’, The Journal of Philosophy 84 (September 1987), 486.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The case of Tourette’s syndrome is especially worrisome because the ‘inability’ concerned is difficult to define, and relative. People who suffer from the syndrome are often able to constrain themselves and to control their ‘uncontrollable’ impulses, but only with extreme effort. Some people are even able to ‘integrate’ the syndrome to a high degree in their personality. Hence, although it is not literally impossible for them to behave quietly and inconspicuously, it would be unreasonable to expect it of them because it would demand an inhuman effort. Hence, our expectations of one another take into account not only our individual abilities but also the effort it costs us to exercise them.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. B. Gert, T. J. Duggan, ‘Free Will as the Ability to Will’, Noûs 13 (1979), 197217.

    Google Scholar 

  15. P. Benson, op. cit., 465–486

    Google Scholar 

  16. R. J. Wallace, op. cit., 41.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Elsewhere I argue that the general assumption that we are deeply responsible human beings can be justified on the basis of the necessity of a certain modesty with respect to the legitimacy of our normative expectations, see Maureen Sie, Responsibility, Blameworthy Actions and Normative Disagreements (Utrecht University, Ph.D. thesis, 1999), chapter 4.

    Google Scholar 

  18. S. Wolf, op. cit., chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  19. D. C. Dennett, ‘Conditions of Personhood’, The Identities of Persons, A.O. Rorty (ed.) ( Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976 ), 194.

    Google Scholar 

  20. There is a difficulty with regard to our moral sentiments towards so-called moral monsters, but I do not think it would be very difficult to provide an error-account in these cases.

    Google Scholar 

  21. R. Chisholm, ‘Human Freedom and the Self, The Lindley Lectures ( Department of Philosophy, University of Kansas, 1964 ), 25.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Primarily directed at Wolf, op. cit., who accepts the necessity of alternate possibilities with regard to the category of blameworthy actions but argues that it is perfectly reasonable to treat it as compatible with determinism until ‘otherwise is proven,’ because psychological freedom is not necessarily incompatible with physiological determinism, and psychological determinism is not very likely to be true. Cf. criticism of C. Grau, ‘Moral Responsibility and S. Wolf s Ability’, this volume; M. Ravizza, J. M. Fischer, ‘Responsibility, Freedom, and Reason’, Ethics 102 (Jan. 1992), 385–88.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Primarily directed against R. J. Wallace, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  24. I thank Jan Bransen, Bert van den Brink, Christopher Grau, Marc Slors and Susan Wolf for commenting on and discussing earlier versions of this contribution. I also thank Ton van den Beld for his helpful corrections and comments.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sie, M. (2000). Freedom and Blameworthiness. In: van den Beld, T. (eds) Moral Responsibility and Ontology. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 7. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2361-9_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2361-9_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5435-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2361-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics