Skip to main content

Maimonidean Naturalism

  • Chapter
Maimonides and the Sciences

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 211))

Abstract

A telling criticism of the mechanistic tradition in science is made by Pierre Teilhard de Chardin in his celebrated cosmological meditation, The Phenomenon of Man.1 Natural scientists have concerned themselves largely, perhaps exclusively, with just one of the two basic forms of energy of which we are aware, the outwardly directed or “tangential” energy by which bodies affect one another. The inwardly focused or “radial” energies by which things are centered and integrated in themselves and through which they are drawn, in seeming defiance of the second law of thermodynamics, towards ever higher levels of complexity and integration, have been neglected or ignored. All energy, Teilhard remarks, almost incidentally, must be assumed to be psychic in nature. But the radial sort, as the foundation of heightened complexity, is the prototype of consciousness.

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the International Conference on Neoplatonism and Jewish Thought, Honolulu, 1987, and published in the proceedings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. London: Collins, 1959, 62–66.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Shmuel Sambursky, Physics of the Stoics (London: Routledge Kegal Paul), 1959, 1–48.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Enneads V 3.15; cf. III 8.10, 2; V 4.2, 38.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Maimonides, Guide II 12; and cf. Ibn Tufayl’s Hayy Ibn Yagzän, tr. L.E. Goodman (Boston: Twayne, 1972; repr. Los Angeles, 1991), 125–127.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Guide III 16.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Guide III 16; cf. 117, 28, II 13. Maimonides follows Saadiah’s lead in treating theodicy as one of the few legitimate problem areas in theology. He follows Aristotle himself, but more specifically the tradition we know as represented by al-Kindî and al-Amirî, in assimilating First Philosophy to theology. See Dimitri Gutas, Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition (Leiden: Brill, 1988) 238–53; Everett Rowson, A Muslim Philosopher on the Soul and its Fate. Of the two major families of issues addressed in the Guide to the Perplexed — the Account of Creation and the Account of the Chariot — Maimonides treats the former as a special case of the latter: The problems of cosmology and cosmogony (philosophical “Physics”) are a subset of the problems of theophany, God’s manifestation in finite terms (metaphysics or theology). Rival schools of thought — creationism, interventionistic occasionalism, the laissez faire theology of the Epicureans and the eternalistic naturalism of the Aristotelians — accordingly lead to corresponding positions with regard to providence and creation. The idea that the principal problem of metaphysics is the emergence of the many from the one is, of course, neoplatonic.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Joseph Owens, The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics, 3rd ed. (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies), 1978, 315–74.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Dillon traces the placement of the Forms in the mind of God as far back as the Middle Platonists and ultimately to Plato himself: The Middle Platonists 6, 95, 255, 410, with Timaeus 35A,Laws X. Plotinus fuses Aristotle’s Nous with Plato’s realm of forms, referring to the now content-filled thought-thinking-itself as Being. The synthesis of Alexander of Aphrodisias was crucial in making the transcendental intelligibles objects of the thought of Nous.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Metaphysics A 9, 991a8: “Above all one might discuss the question what on earth the Forms contributechwr(133) For they cause neither movement nor any changechwr(133)” Peirce is one of the few modern thinkers to take cognizance of theories of the type we are discussing. He writes (in a paragraph cancelled by Langley but restored by Wiener): “Another philosophy which had some currency in England in Hume’s time was the theory of a `plastic nature,’ that is to say, a slightly intelligent agent, intermediate between God and the universe, God’s factotum, which attended to the ordinary routine of administration of the universe. This theory was so much out of date that I should not have mentioned it were it not that I suspect it aided considerably in bringing into vogue the phrase law of nature’ in England, an expression which the sectaries of the plastic nature might very naturally, and in fact early did employ. One of them, for example, Lord Brooke, in a work published in 1633chwr(133)” C.S. Peirce, ed. P. Wiener, 297. I am indebted to Jim Tiles for the foregoing reference. Peirce has little use for Brooke’s line of thinking, finding its explanatory principles too non-specific (or tautologous!). But since the aim was not directly to explain effects but to mediate between the universal and the particular, the concept remained in use down to the 18th century.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Philo, following Platonic, Stoic, Rabbinic and Scriptural hints and suggestions, is clearly an architect of the approach, for his logos partakes of both of objective and subjective rationality and thus mediates between the absoluteness of God and the finite particularity of the world. Philo, like Maimonides, calls the ideas powers, following Sophist 247DE; he makes them subordinate to God and in effect answers Aristotle’s charge (n. 9 above) by treating the ideas as the active (energoun), organizing principles of nature. See De Mutatione Nominum 21, 122 and De Specialibus Legihus 18, 45–48 and H.A. Wolfson, Philo, 1.217–18; cf. David Winston, citing Phaedo 95E and Diogenes Laertius 7, 147 in Logos and Mystical Theology in Philo of Alexandria (Cincinnati: Hebrew Union College Press, 1985), 19.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The identification is not confined to the Guide to the Perplexed. See Maimonides Code, I, Hilkhot Yesodei Torah 2.7, ed. and tr. M. Hyamson (Jerusalem: Feldheim, 1974) 36a, where the highest echelon of angels, the scriptural haryot, are called forms ( urot).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Guide II 6, Munk, 2.17b, II, 14–17.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Guide II 6, Munk 2.I7b, II, 5–6. The usage which refers to emanative energies as forces or powers is precedented in Arabic in al-Fârâbi’s F Aql (De Intellectu et Intellecto), ed., M. Bouyges (Beirut: Catholic Press, 1939); tr. A. Hyman, in Arthur Hyman and James Walsh, eds. Philosophy in the Middle Ages (New York: Harper and Row, 1967), 211–21.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Guide II 5, citing Psalms 19:2–4.

    Google Scholar 

  15. For the complementarity of rationalism and empiricism in this type of account of knowledge and discovery, see my Avicenna (London: Routledge, 1992), chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Guide II 4, Munk 2.14ab; II 48, citing Jonah 2:2.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Guide 1I 6, Munk 2.176, II. 1–3; cf. De Generatione Animalium 11 3, 7366 26–737a I1.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Thus 1 Kings 19:11–12: “chwr(133) and the Lord was not in the windchwr(133) the Lord was not in the earthquakechwr(133) the Lord was not in the fire: and after the fire was a still small voicechwr(133)” Maimonides cites the passage in Guide II 41 in justifying his account of prophecy, which neither reduces prophetic inspiration to a matter of subjective appearances nor treats it as a matter of divine indwelling but relies upon the (creationist) mediating scheme of (neoplatonic, intellectual/formal) angels between the divine Absoluteness and human intelligence.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Guide II 6, Munk 2.166–17a. The Rabbinic text Maimonides cites echoes Sanhedrin 38b but the verbatim citation is unknown. The celestial retinue are called God’s pamalva (cf. the Latin famulus), servitors or ministrants, not peers. Plato speaks of the creator (i.e. the demiurge) consulting the forms at Timaeus 28b, 29ab, 30c.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Guide III 18.

    Google Scholar 

  21. De Anima III 4, 429a 15–16, 430a 3, 5, 430a 17–20: Guide 1 68, Munk 1.86b; Code I, Hilkhot Yesodei Torah 2.10.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Guide I 48. Philo reaches a similar conclusion.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Guide III 21.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Guide III 19.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Guide III 19, Munk 3.40.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Guide III 16, Munk 3.43b-44a.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Guide II 6, Munk 2.16–18.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. al-Ghazâlï, Tahâfut al-Falâsifa, The Incoherence of the Philosophers, ed. M. Bouyges (Beirut: Catholic Press, 2nd edn., 1962): “Our second point addresses those who grant that these events flow (or emanate) from the First Principles of temporal events..”

    Google Scholar 

  29. This is what Peirce, perhaps recognizing its Islamic origins, called “explanation à la Turque”; ed. Wiener, 296.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Guide III 17, II 13; cf. III 31.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Guide III 13, I 1; “Eight Chapters” 5, echoing Plato’s Theaetetus 176.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Guide III 32. Cf. Miskawayh, The Refinement of Character,tr. Constantine Zurayk (Beirut: American University, 1968), 81–83 and my discussion in “Humanism and Islamic Ethics: The Curious Case of Miskawayh,” in Brian Carr, ed., Morals and Society in Asian Philosophy, (London: Curzon, 1996), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Guide II 20, citing Physics II 4–5; and Guide II 12, 48.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Guide II 3, 10, 12. For God’s “will” and “wisdom,” see my “Matter and Form as Attributes of God in Maimonides’ Philosophy,” in R. Link-Salinger et al., eds., A Straight Path: Essays in Honor of Arthur Hyman (Washington: Catholic University Press, 1988), 86–97.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See Guide I 2, II 4.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Guide II 17; cf. III 15.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Guide I 72, II 10.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Maimonides Code I, Hilkhot Teshuvah 5.2, 5.1, 5.4 viii, Hyamson, 86b-87b; cf. my Jewish and Islamic Philosophy: Crosspollinations in the Classical Age (Edinburgh University Press and Rutgers University Press, 1999), 146–200. For animal vitality see Guide I 72, Munk 1.102b 1. 17–103a I. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Guide II 5, Munk 2.15ab. Maimonides emphasizes the inanimateness of the four elements in Guide I 72 and argues that if the elements were alive and the forces of nature exercised discretion, confining their actions only to what is necessary, there would be no natural evils.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See Guide III 22.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Guide II 6, Munk 2.16b I. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Guide 172, Munk 1.100b.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See Qur’an 2:34 and the commentaries; for Shiite views, M.J. Kister, “Legends in tafsir and hadith Literature: the Creation of Adam and Related Stories,” in Andrew Rippin, ed., Approaches to the History of the Interpretation of the Qur än (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), 108–9.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Guide II, 11, III 12–14. The spheres, being composed of matter, are “impure” relative to the disembodied intellects; but even the spheres are nobler as bodies than human bodies are: They do not exist for our sake. For the nobility of the spheres and intellects, see Abraham Ibn Daud, The Exalted Faith, ed. and tr. Norbert Samuelson and Gershon Weiss (Rutherford: Fairleigh Dickenson University Press, 1986), 120b.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Guide II 7, Munk 2.18b. Cf. Saadiah, on Job 1:6 in Goodman, tr., The Book of Theodicy, 15459.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Guide II 6, Munk 2.17ab. Note the terminological affinity of Maimonides’ `formative power’ and the `plastic nature’ mentioned by Peirce.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Guide 1I 6, Munk 2.18b.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Guide II, Introduction, Premises 10–12. Natural forms are “forces in a body,” but the substantial forms through which a body exists — soul and mind, for example — are not forces in a body or divided even per accidens with its divisions (cf. Aristotle, De Anima I 5, 41lb 19–27). Maimonides accepts all the premises of the Philosophers, except the eternity of the world, which he treats as an isolable postulate of their system.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See Guide II 4, 5, 7, 8, esp. II 5, citing Psalms 19:4, Munk 2.15b.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Phaedo 97C–98E. Socrates assumed that if he knew how all things are governed for the best and thus what is best for each, he would know how human beings too should be governed. Cf. Maimonides’ understanding of Moses’ desire to learn God’s ways (the laws of nature), so as to know how to govern the people: Guide I 54, glossing Exodus 33:13–20 and 34:6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Metaphysics 1 3, 984a 11–19, 985a 18; cf. De Anima 1 2, 405a 14–17; Poetica 15, 1454b 1.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Metaphysics 14, 985a 5–29.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Cf. al-Fârâbî, Kitâb Mabâdï’ ârâ’ ahlu ‘l-madînatu ‘1-Fâd ila (The Book of the Principles behind the Beliefs of the People of the Outstanding State) III 9, ix. R. Walzer as Al-Fârâbî on the Perfect State, 145–49.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Guide II 4.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Guide II 19, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  56. The Incoherence of the Philosophers, Discussions 3–4, 10; see my “Al-Ghazâlî’s Argument from Creation,” International Journal of Middle Eastern Studies 2 (1971) 67–85, 168 88; “Did al-Ghazâlî Deny Causality?” Studia Islamica 47 (1978) 83–120; RAMBAM, 175–204.

    Google Scholar 

  57. See Metaphysics 1046b, 1048a 8–12, and Maimonides, Guide II 19; “Eight Chapters,” 8; Code,1, Hilkhot Teshuvah 5.2, with 5.1 and 5.4 viii; see my discussion in Jewish and Islamic Philosophy: Crosspollinations in the Classical Age, pp. 146–200.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Guide III 17.5 and Deuteronomy 11:26.

    Google Scholar 

  59. To affirm an open future is not to affirm the actuality of alternative futures but only the reality of alternative possibilities as possibilities - that is, their virtuality. See my “Leibniz and Futurity,” in Leibniz and Adam, ed. M. Dascal and E. Yakira (Tel Aviv: University Publishing, 1993), 301–324. If we adopt the notion of emergence portended in Bergson’s idea of duration or even in Spinoza’s dynamism with regard to the conatus, we can say that even if only one future will be actual, there are a variety of alternative possibilities for that future, since its nature does not become determinate until it exists, that is, until its causes make it actual.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Cf. “Eight Chapters,” 8, citing Deuteronony 22:8.

    Google Scholar 

  61. If the position sounds Leibnizian, there is good reason: see my “Maimonides and Leibniz,” with Leibniz’ reading notes on the Latin Doctor Perplexorum (Basel, 1629).

    Google Scholar 

  62. I say all but infinitely painstaking care, because had infinite care been taken, the task could not have been completed and finite being could not have emerged. Finitude would have been overwhelmed. Cf. David Novak’s paper in L.E. Goodman, ed. Neoplatonism and Jewish Thought, (Albany: SUNY Press, 1992), 299–318.

    Google Scholar 

  63. TF 197–98.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Guide III 18.

    Google Scholar 

  65. See my God of Abraham (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), 240–241.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Guide II 20.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Cf. my discussion of the incoherence of positivism in God of Abraham, 73–78.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Guide III 25.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See Arthur Hyman’s paper in Neoplatonism and Jewish Thought (Albany, SUNY Press, 1992), 111–135.

    Google Scholar 

  70. See Guide II 12, citing Jeremiah 2:13, Psalms 36:10; Guide 168. The ideas of light, life, being and truth, come together in the Psalmist’s fused image a fountain of life which is the source of our enlightenment - the image in which Ibn Gabirol saw the affinity of Biblical poetry to Neoplatonie metaphysics. The elaboration of the intuition is the substance of Ibn Gabirol’s metaphysics, as set forth in the papers of Professors Dillon, Mathis and McGinn in Neoplatonism and Jewish Thought.

    Google Scholar 

  71. See Guide III 21.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Cf. Guide I 23, 65.

    Google Scholar 

  73. For Plato insisted that all temporal things are mutable, and Maimonides urged that one cannot make a metaphysical canon of the observed stability of kinds in nature. See Guide II 17, 14; cf. Maimonides’ suggestive gloss of Genesis Rabbah XXI at Guide 1 49: “Through this dictum they state clearly that the angels [se. forms] are immaterial and have no fixed bodily form outside the mind.” Munk 1.556 II 2–4. For what is fixed, by Platonic standards must be ideal, and what is mutable must be sensory and so imaginable.

    Google Scholar 

  74. See Aristotle, Physics IV 2; al-Ghazâlî, Ma’ârij al-Quds 203–04; Tahâfut al-Falâsifa (Incoherence of the Philosophers) Bouyges 2nd ed., 67; Guide I 52.

    Google Scholar 

  75. See Guide I 71, Munk 1.96a.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Themistii in Aristotelis Metaphysicorum librum Lambda paraphrasis, Medieval Hebrew translation, ed. S. Landauer, in Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 5.5 (Berlin, 1903) 8, cited in Herbert Davidson, “Averroes on the Active Intellect,” 202.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See P.S. Schiavella, “Emergent Evolution and Reductionism,” Scientia 108 (1973) 323–330.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Aristotle, Metaphysics Alpha 4, 985a 24.

    Google Scholar 

  79. See Guide III 18, 22; cf. I 68, also I 9, with Saadiah, Book of Critically Chosen Beliefs and Convictions, II 13 ad fin., ed., Kafih, 115, tr. Rosenblatt, 136.

    Google Scholar 

  80. See her edition, translation and commentary of Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), 60, 74, 93–98.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Guide III 13 with Ill 25. But Saadiah does not believe that God made all things for man’s pleasure or entertainment, but so that man can earn salvation and deserve reward and recompense. And he notes, pointedly, that rain falls on the sea, and not just on our fields.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Thus Maimonides’ emphasis on the Aristotelian thesis, still employed by our scientists, that the world forms a single system, and his further emphasis on the Saadianic point that the thesis of the world’s singularity is vital to the central claim of monotheism. See Guide 172.

    Google Scholar 

  83. For Maimonides’ rejection of epicycles and eccentrics, see Guide II 24; cf. I 71, Munk 1.96a; cf. F.J. Carmody, “The Planetary Theory of Ibn Rushd,” Osiris 10 (1952) 556–86; A.I. Sabra, “The Andalusian Revolt against Ptolemaic Astronomy,” in E. Mendelsohn, ed., Transformation and Tradition in the Sciences (Cambridge: at the University Press, 1984) 133–53; Tzvi Langermann, “The True Perplexity of The Guide of the Perplexed: Part II, Chapter 24,” in Joel Kraemer, ed., Perspectives on Maimonides: Philosophical and Historical Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 159–74.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Guide II 3.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Guide II 11. Plato’s likely story account of science is not, of course, a skeptical rejection of the scientific enterprise, but an attempt to explain the nature and limits of what must pass for knowledge within the confines of a temporal, sensory world. See Anne Ashbaugh, Plato’s Theory of Explanation (Albany: SUNY Press, 1988). Maimonides too is no radical skeptic. He accepts Saadiah’s epistemology, and his most distinctive principle of method is the postulate that the possibility of doubt is not sufficient grounds for rejecting a claim.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Guide, II 2, 11. At II 8 Maimonides cites a passage now lost in Talmud texts, at Pesahim 94b, “The sages of the nations prevailed,” to show that the Rabbis conceded the authority of secular science in astronomy and other natural sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Guide I 72, II 4-5. Averroes gives the same diffident approval of cosmic emanation that we find in Maimonides, bracketing such speculations as the work of “recent philosophers such as alFârâbî,” perhaps along with the ideas of Themistius and Plato, yet calling them “the most solid” notions we have to go on in these rather unsolid areas. Madrid Escorial Hebrew manuscript G1-14, fol. 103b, etc. cited in Davidson, “Averroes on the Active Intellect,” n. 40. Al-Fârâbi himself characteristically brackets metaphysical views which have an impact on cosmology as “beliefs of the people of the excellent state.” See Ara’, and Fusid al-Madani.

    Google Scholar 

  88. See God of Abraham, Chapter 8.

    Google Scholar 

  89. See my “Ordinary and Extraordinary Language in Medieval Jewish and Islamic Philosophy.”

    Google Scholar 

  90. See the chapter on creativity in my Truth (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  91. See De Partibus Animalium I 5, esp. 645a 9.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Cf. De Partibus Animalium I 1, 640b 30 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Here I refer to the profound insight articulated in Cynthia Ozick’s story, “The Laughter of Akiva,” in its original recension in the New Yorker 56 (November 10, 1980, et seq.), 50–60+.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Goodman, L.E. (2000). Maimonidean Naturalism. In: Cohen, R.S., Levine, H. (eds) Maimonides and the Sciences. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 211. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2128-8_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2128-8_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5348-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2128-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics