Skip to main content

Metaphilosophical Skepticism and the Teaching of Philosophy

  • Chapter
Book cover Knowledge, Teaching and Wisdom

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 67))

Abstract

There is a tradition in philosophy, certainly in the analytic tradition, and perhaps stretching back to antiquity, in which the teaching of philosophy is thought to require a certain form of neutrality. A philosophy teacher should not take it as a goal of the teaching of philosophy that students be converted to any particular philosophical doctrine, or that they be sustained in any of their preexisting opinions. The point of teaching philosophy is not that students should become theists, ethical cognitivists, libertarians, reductive materialists, nor indeed that they adopt any particular philosophical stance. Instead, the successful teacher of philosophy forces students to think critically about a philosophical position and its competitors. I have, at least implicitly, always taken such a thesis of neutrality to be an orthodox and obvious tenet of the philosophy of teaching philosophy. Nonetheless, I have recently found colleagues, particularly those with passionate religious, political or ethical beliefs, who were in less than full agreement with this “received” tradition of philosophical neutrality. I still wish to maintain my orthodoxy, but can no longer expect other philosophers to agree with it unless the position can be adequately articulated and defended. In order to understand what is at issue, and to answer some sophisticated critics of this received tradition, we must become clearer on the epistemic status of philosophical opinion. I would maintain that the neutrality incumbent on the teaching of philosophy is a consequence of a skepticism with respect to philosophy itself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. In “Therapeutic Arguments”: Epicurus and Aristotle” in The Norms of Nature,Malcolm Schofield and Gisela Striker, eds., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). I do not, however, maintain that Nussbaum’s view of Epicurus’s teaching is historically accurate.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See George Chatalian’s Epistemology and Skepticism (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991) for a defense of the view that the skepticism of ancient skeptics is quite limited and does not involve the doubting of these claims of common sense.

    Google Scholar 

  3. For example, Paul Churchland, who in Matter and Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford Books, 1984) develops an eliminativist theory of mind.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Socrates: 201CI should make use of premises which the person interrogated would be willing to admit.” Meno, 76d, Benjamin Jowett, tr., ( Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1977 ).

    Google Scholar 

  5. A move John Pollock recommends against general skepticism in Contemporary Theories of Knowledge,(Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman & Littlefield, 1986), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  6. David Lewis, “Introduction,” Philosophical Papers, vol, I (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), x.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Peter van Inwagen, in “Quam Dilecta,” in God and the Philosophers,Thomas V. Morris, ed., (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994), considers the facts I make use of in this argument, though he draws back from a skeptical conclusion. He conjectures that what justifies him in accepting a philosophical thesis might be a special sort of insight that is not present in those who disagree with him. Compare my argument to one by Sextus, “So whenever I say ‘To every argument an equal argument is opposed,’ what I am virtually saying is ‘To every argument investigated by me which establishes a point dogmatically, it seems to me there is opposed another argument establishing a point dogmatically, which is equal to the first in respect of credibility and incredibility’; so that the utterance of the phrase is not a piece of dogmatism, but the announcement of a human state of mind which is apparent to the person experiencing it” Sextus Empiricus,4 vols., Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1933), book 1 of Outlines of Pyrhonism,p. 203, R. G. Bury, trans., quotation and citation from Chatalian, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Though I trust the term defeaterhas an intuitive sense, I am actually using the term here in a way consistent with a technical term of epistemologists. John Pollock, in Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1986), p. 38, defines the notion of one proposition or belief defeating another as follows:

    Google Scholar 

  9. In order for us to have a defeater for our philosophical justifications, we must have reason to think that other philosophers are in analogous epistemic situations to ourselves. Thus, if my colleague were suddenly to maintain that he has discovered an argument for solipsism that he thinks cogent and I think mad, I may have reason to think that he is not in an epistemically analogous situation. The situation is akin to a perceptual one. If my colleague were to confuse his wife with a hat, as did the unfortunate man in Oliver Sacks The Man Who Mistook His Wife for a Hat,(New York: Harper and Row, 1985), I would similarly have good reason to think he is not in an epistemically analogous situation. Yet, if several individuals whom I take to have as good a musical ear as mine were to think they hear the oboes at a point in the symphony where I hear only clarinets, then I would have good reason to doubt my perceptual belief.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Julia Annas Stoic Epistemology in Epistemology, Companions to Ancient Thought: 1,Stephen Everson, ed., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 186–188.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ross, G. (1996). Metaphilosophical Skepticism and the Teaching of Philosophy. In: Lehrer, K., Lum, B.J., Slichta, B.A., Smith, N.D. (eds) Knowledge, Teaching and Wisdom. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 67. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2022-9_19

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2022-9_19

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4684-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2022-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics