Skip to main content

Should Natural-Language Definitions be Insulated from, or Interactive with, One Another in Sentence Composition?

  • Chapter
Knowledge and Language

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 227))

  • 214 Accesses

Abstract

It is often assumed that the fundamental question about definition concerns how different kinds of definition — ostensive definition, stipulative definition, dictionary definition, etc. — should be structured. But, unless we first determine how definitions should be expected to function, we cannot hope to arrive at a satisfactory account of how they should be structured. We need to know how a mechanism is intended to behave before we can work usefully on its design. This paper will therefore be concerned with one important aspect of the prior issue. Specifically, when a particular set of lexical definitions, in a particular syntactic framework, is supposed to compose the meaning of a given sentence, should those definitions be supposed to operate independently of one another or not?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. L. Jonathan Cohen, ‘How is conceptual innovation possible?’, Erkenntnis 25, 1986, pp. 223ff. The distinction has been fruitfully taken up by E. F. Kittay, Metaphor: Its Cognitive Force and Linguistic Structure,Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987, esp. p. 110ff.

    Google Scholar 

  2. F. de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics,ed. C. Bally and A. Sechehaye, trans. W. Baskin, New York: Philosophical Library, 1959, 88–89. See L. J. Cohen, ‘Chess as a Model for Language’, Philosophy 11, 1982, 51–87.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See, for example, A. Garnham, Psycholinguistics: Central Topics, London: Methuen, 1985, 190–195.

    Google Scholar 

  4. J. D. Atlas, Philosophy Without Ambiguity: A Logico-Linguistic Essay, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  5. A. N. Whitehead and B. Russell, Principia Mathematica, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See G. Frege, ‘On Sense and Reference’, in P. Geach and M. Black (eds.), Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, Oxford: Blackwell, 1952, 5678.

    Google Scholar 

  7. A. Church, ‘A formulation of the logic of sense and denotation’, in P. Henle, H. M. Kallen, and S. K. Langer (eds.), Structure, Method and Meaning: Essays in Honour of Henry M. Sheffer, New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1951, pp. 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Plato, Republic 597b, and Aristotle, Categories ad irait

    Google Scholar 

  9. The Compact Edition of the Oxford English Dictionary,Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971, is somewhat inconsistent in its practice. For example: it lists representational senses for ‘lion’ and ‘tiger’ but not for ‘giraffe’ and ‘zebra’.

    Google Scholar 

  10. C.L. Stevenson, Ethics and Language, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1944, and R.M. Hare, The Language of Morals, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  11. D. Davidson, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 245–264.

    Google Scholar 

  12. J. L. Austin, How to Do Thing with Words,Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962, 101ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See.I.R. Searle, Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979, 92 123.

    Google Scholar 

  14. .1. R. Searle, ‘Metaphor’, in A. Ortony (ed.), Metaphor and Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979, 92–123.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., 100.

    Google Scholar 

  16. no longer think it possible to give a distinctive-feature account of metaphorical meaning as proposed in L. J. Cohen, ‘The Semantics of Metaphor’, in A. Ortony (ed.), op. cit., 64–77. What inescapably block it are examples like (25), where indisputably factual, rather than linguistic, knowledge is invoked.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See L. J. Cohen, ‘The Individuation of Proper Names’ in Z. van Straaten (ed.), Philosophical Subjects, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 140–163.

    Google Scholar 

  18. R. Montague, Formal Philosophy,1974, New Haven: Yale University Press, 188.

    Google Scholar 

  19. L. J. Cohen, ‘A Problem about Ambiguity in Truth-functional Semantics’, Analysis 45, 1985, 129–134.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cohen, L.J. (2002). Should Natural-Language Definitions be Insulated from, or Interactive with, One Another in Sentence Composition?. In: Knowledge and Language. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 227. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2020-5_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2020-5_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5955-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2020-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics