Skip to main content

Can the Logic of Indirect Discourse be Formalised?

  • Chapter
Knowledge and Language

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 227))

  • 216 Accesses

Abstract

Recent attempts1 to analyse or explicate assertion-statements and other kinds of indirect discourse in formal terms seem to have overlooked an even greater difficulty than the familiar problems arising about equivalence, synonymy, translatability, etc. This difficulty is created by the fact that in judicial, journalistic, or historical fact-finding, as well as in everyday conversation, we frequently cite statements about a witness’s truthfulness alongside the report of his testimony as the premisses from which we argue about the facts. It is then an essential part of our argument that it should appear to jump from one level of statement to another, and perhaps back again. So that the difficulty emerges: how can the formalisation of such an argument adopt any of the usual hierarchy-principles as a guarantee against semantical antinomies?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. E.g., R. Carnap,Meaning and necessity (1947) p. 83 ff.; A. Church, “On Carnap’s analysis of statements of assertion and belief”, Analysis 10 (1950) p. 97 ff., and “Intensional isomorphism and identity of belief”, Philosophical studies 5 (1954) p. 65 ff.; I. Scheffier, “On synonymy and indirect discourse”, Philosophy of science 12 (1955) p. 39 ff.; etc.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Mathematical logic(1951) p. 2 (cf. the same author’s “Truth by convention” in Philosophical essays for A. N. Whitehead,1936, p. 90 ff.) If what Quine says here is to afford, informally, a necessary and sufficient criterion of logical truth under all circumstances he needs to make certain further stipulations, such as that in most cases (which need to be further specified) the same word occurs vacuously more than once only if it can be replaced by a word having precisely the same sense and reference on each occurrence in the statement. But these stipulations are not specially relevant to the purpose of the present paper and are therefore not discussed here.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A formulation of the logic of sense and denotation“ in Structure, method, and meaning (1951) ed. P. Henle et al. p. 3 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  4. In any case our axiom would have to be rather stronger than Russell’s, and its justification correspondingly even more questionable (cf. F. P. Ramsey, The foundations of mathematics,1931, p. 28 ff.), since, in order to formalise indirect discourse we should need (for familiar reasons) an order containing properties designated by functions that were not merely extensionally equivalent to all functions designating properties that belonged to other orders of the same type, but also synonymous with them. Moreover, it appears that even Russell’s Axiom permits some of the semantical antinomies to reappear unless the names of some functions are omitted. (cf. I. M. Copi “The inconsistency or redundancy of Principia mathematica” in Philosophy and phenomenological research 11, 1950, pp. 190–9 and the review of this by A. Church in this JOURNAL, vol. 16 1951, pp. 154–5). Yet such an omission would seriously impoverish any formalised language that sets out to be as rich as the everyday natural languages in which indirect discourse is ordinarily articulated.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. L. J. Cohen and A. C. Lloyd, “Assertion statements”, Analysis 15 (1955) p. 68. The main argument developed in Assertion statements reinforces, though is less powerful than, the present paper’s argument about the difficulty in principle of formalising indirect discourse. But in (D) of the present paper a way round this difficulty is discussed which was not mentioned in Assertion statements.

    Google Scholar 

  6. I allude in particular to certain problems about the interpretation of modal calculi which I hope to discuss elsewhere. The procedure discussed here is also indispensable for a third kind of proposal for formalising indirect discourse, unlike either Church’s or Carnap’s, which is sometimes found in the literature. In the analysans for, say, ’x asserts that p’ the prefatory phrase ‘asserts that’ or ’x asserts that’ is sometimes not represented by a predicate at all neither by an object-language function taking as one of its arguments the name of an intensional entity nor by a metalinguistic function taking as one of its arguments the name of a sentence in the object-language but by a non-extensional operator forming statements out of statements. A paper by Los on a system of this sort was reviewed in this Journal 14 (1949) pp. 64–5, and another such system is proposed by A. N. Prior in Time and modality (1957) p. 130–1. I have been unable to consult Los’s paper and Prior’s somewhat summary description of his system does not indicate explicitly how he intends to avoid the occurrence of semantical antinomies in interpreting it. But it is clear that no hierarchy principle controls the way in which Prior’s operators form statements out of statements, since one category of these operators forms truth-functions of the statements they precede and even those that are prefaces to indirect discourse may precede any other such preface. Indeed, in a formalised language based on this system the analysis of (1) would be quite straightforward. The analysans is CKrylïpCÀpNpóEpKryppK EpKrypNpEpKópp where ‘7’ and ’ó’ are interpreted as the operators ’the policeman testifies that’ and ’the prisoner deposes that,’ respectively; and the formal deduction of the consequent from the antecedent of this conditional marches step by step with the informal deduction set out above. But a policy like that outlined in (D) must be pursued if ’EpKópNp’ is not to generate a contradiction when ‘7’ is interpreted as ’I am now asserting that’ (with ’now’ in a narrow sense).

    Google Scholar 

  7. When a set is referred to by an expression that contravenes a hierarchy principle like Russell’s theory of types or Quine’s stratification requirement, another mode of referring to the set may be sought that is unobjectionable on these grounds. But the referentially opaque quality of indirect discourse precludes in general any analogous method of avoiding difficulties in formalising indirect discourse according to a hierarchy principle. One may, however, observe a rough and distant analogy between the way in which (D) above seeks to avoid the semantical antinomies by specifying conditions under which a predicate letter in a syntactically well-formed formula is to be assigned a meaning and the way in which set theories in the Zermelo tradition seek to avoid the logical antinomies by setting up conditions under which a predicate is to be viewed as having an extension.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. S. C. Kleene, Introduction to metamathematics (1952) p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cohen, L.J. (2002). Can the Logic of Indirect Discourse be Formalised?. In: Knowledge and Language. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 227. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2020-5_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2020-5_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5955-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2020-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics