Skip to main content

Carnap on Logic and Experience

  • Chapter
History of Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook [2001] ((VCIY,volume 9))

  • 541 Accesses

Abstract

In recent years, attention for the work of Rudolf Carnap has shifted from polemical discussion to placing Carnap in his intellectual context. Thus, the central question is no longer whether Carnap contributes to solving our current problems, but whether he solved the problems of his day and age. This contextualist approach has resulted in a deeper and more refined understanding of, in particular, Carnap’s early works and has focused on Der logische Aufbau der Welt.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. E.g., Goodman’s and Quine’s well-known worry about the “at”-relation employed in §§126127.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Rudolf Camap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Berlin: Weltkreis-Verlag 1928, §16; the notion of “structure” is introduced in §12. As has been pointed out by Friedman and others, Camap’s goal in the Aufbau is to show that at least one constitution system is possible. This means, among other things, that Carnap is concerned with showing that there is at least one way of casting all of science in a purely structural form.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Camap, Aufbau,00A712.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Camap, Aufbau, 00A7 00A7153–155.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Michael Friedman, “Camap’s Aufbau reconsidered”, in: Noûs 21, 1987, p.533; Alan Richardson, Carnap’s Construction of the World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998, p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  6. My presentation in this section owes a lot to the following papers: Thomas Ryckman, “Conditio Sine Qua Non? Zuordnung in the Early Epistemologies of Cassirer and Schlick”, in: Synthese 88, 1991, pp.57–95, and Don Howard, “Relativity, Eindeutigkeit,and Monomorphism: Rudolf Carnap and the Development of the Categoricity Concept in Formal Semantics”, in:Ronald N. Giere/Alan W. Richardson (eds.), Origins of Logical Empiricism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1996, pp.115–164. These papers elucidate the concepts of “co-ordination” and “univocalness”, respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Göran Sundholm suggested to me that “correlation” may be a better translation of Zuordnung. Although `correlation“ is used in Blumberg’s translation of Schlick’s Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, I will stick with the more usual `co-ordination” here.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Compare “The connection between members [of a series] is in any case created by means of some general law of co-ordination…”,(Emst Cassirer, Substanzbegrii f and Funktionsbegrff Berlin: Bruno Cassirer 1910, p.21) with “The manifold of sensations is co-ordinated with the manifold of real objects in such a way that every connection that can be established in one totality indicates a connection in the other.” (ibid.,pp.404–5) Since the connections co-ordinated in this way are referred to as `co-ordinations“ themselves, the ambiguity is clear.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The elements, which we first obtained from intuition, have to be analysed ever more thoroughly, they must be resolved ever more completely in purely conceptual definitions in order to become truly objects of mathematical consideration. Thus intuition, wherever we appeal to it, does not constitute the proper ground of truth of theorems. It is rather like an ultimate unresolved remainder, which awaits further division and operation by thought; it is the goal that points the way for our purely logical formation of concepts.“ (Ernst Cassirer, ”Kant and die moderne Mathematik“, in: Kantstudien 17, 1907, pp.29–30). All translations from German texts in this paper are my own, unless a translation is mentioned in the reference.

    Google Scholar 

  10. That Schlick is aware of the problem of univocalness is clear from: “(…) the individual entity is to be designated uniquely with the help only of the most general names (…)” (Moritz Schlick, General Theory of Knowledge. transl. by A.E. Blumberg, Wien: Springer Verlag, 1974, p.14.)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Schlick, op.cit.,p.32.

    Google Scholar 

  12. The co-ordinating of two objects with one another, the relating of one to the other, is in fact a fundamental act of consciousness, not reducible to anything else. It is a simple ultimate that can only be stated, a limit and a basis, which every epistemologist must ultimately press toward.“ (Schlick, op.cit.,p.383) Schlick is quite outspoken on the elimination of pure intuition: ”(…) we have looked in vain for a pure intuition that might serve as the basis for empirical intuition by supplying it with its form and lawfulness.“ (ibid.,p.358)

    Google Scholar 

  13. These terms are listed in the references of: Rudolf Carnap, Der Raum. Ein Beitrag zur Wissenschaftslehre. Kantstudien Erganzungsheft Nr.56, ( Berlin: Reuther and Reichard, 1922 ), p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Carnap, Der Raum,p.61.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Carnap, Der Raum,p.23.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Rudolf Carnap, “Über die Aufgabe der Physik”, in: Kantstudien 28, 1923, pp.90–107; Rudolf Carnap, “Dreidimensionalität des Raumes und Kausalität”, in: Annalen der Philosophie und philosophischen Kritik,4, 1924, pp.105–130; Rudolf Carnap, “Über die Abhängigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der Zeit”, in: Kantstudien 30, 1925, pp.331–345; Rudolf Carnap, “Eigentliche und uneigentliche Begriffe”, in: Symposion I, 1927, pp.355–374.

    Google Scholar 

  17. physics expresses itself neutrally by means of a purely formal relation of co-ordination“ (”Über die Aufgabe“, loc.cit.,p. 100); ”The relation between this kind of experience of the second stage and that of the first stage is produced by co-ordination“ (”Dreidimensionalitat“, loc. cit.,p.107)

    Google Scholar 

  18. In fact, Carnap shows that the principle of simplicity can be applied in one of two forms (“Über die Aufgabe”, loc.cit.,pp.103–105)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid.,p.106.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid,p.107.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Compare Schlick’s statement of formalism: “None of the concepts that occur in the theory designate anything real; rather they designate one another in such a fashion that the meaning of a concept consists in a particular constellation of a number of the remaining concepts.” (Schlick, op.cit.,p.37)

    Google Scholar 

  22. The main argument is reconstructed, in slightly different terms than mine, in Howard, loc.cit.,pp.156–160; and Richardson, op.cit.,pp.43–47. Richardson focuses on the contrast with Schlick’s formalism, but he puts little emphasis on the problem of univocalness as the driving force behind Camap’s discontent with it.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Carnap, Aufbau, §136.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Carnap, Aufbau, § 179.

    Google Scholar 

  25. This optimism is expressed elegantly in the well-known railway metaphor of Camap, Aufbau,§ 14: if the structure of the relation of “railway-connectedness” does not suffice to individuate cities, we can first use relations of connectedness by other means of transportation, then “historical” relations, and finally “all concepts from factual disciplines (Realwissenschaften)”. Surprisingly, Carnap resolves the remaining lack of univocalness by stipulating that the difference between cities is a merely subjective one. In my opinion, this might show that Carnap has written this part of the Aufbau while still under the influence of Schlick’s formalism. In §153, apparently written at a later time, Carnap again discusses univocalness in the context of implicit definition, but he claims that a lack of univocalness is highly improbable, not that it would be merely subjective.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Carnap, Aufbau,§95.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cf. Jean van Heijenoort, “Logic as Calculus and Logic as Language”, in: Synthese 17, 1967, pp.324–330 for a discussion of universalism in the work of Frege and the Principia Mathematica.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Carnap, Aufbau, §154.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Logic (including mathematics) consists only of conventional stipulations about the use of signs and of tautologies based on these stipulations.“ (§107); ”Logic does not have a domain of its own at all, but it contains those statements that hold (as tautologies) for all objects of any arbitrary domain.“ (§154)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Bertrand Russell, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, London: Allen and Unwin, 1919, p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Russell, op.cit.,pp.203–205. For Camap, there is well-known autobiographical evidence to support his incomplete apprehension of the Tractatus cf. the passage from the Archives cited by Jodle Proust, “Formal Logic as Transcendental in Camap and Wittgenstein”, in: Noils 21, 1987, p.502.

    Google Scholar 

  32. I would like to thank Michael Friedman, Jaakko Hintikka, David Hyder, Herman Philipse, and Göran Sundholm for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper and the version read during the HOPOS 2000 conference in Vienna. Any mistakes remaining are, of course, purely my own.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Houkes, W. (2002). Carnap on Logic and Experience. In: Heidelberger, M., Stadler, F. (eds) History of Philosophy of Science. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook [2001], vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1785-4_22

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1785-4_22

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5976-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1785-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics