Skip to main content

Canonical Ensembles, Evolution of Competing Species, and the Arrow of Time

  • Chapter

Abstract

At the outset, it may prove helpful to clarify the respective roles of mathematics and philosophy in the study of evolutionary systems. Historically, the two subjects have not always been considered as distinct. (Indeed, when I was a student in Cambridge, applied mathematics was called “natural philosophy”, while philosophy was called “moral science”.) In order to evolve, systems need to be somewhat complex. This complexity forces a certain subtlety on the concepts used to analyze the systems — concepts like “entropy”, “hierarchy”, “fitness” and “species”. Such concepts can easily lead to paradox and confusion if they are not defined and used with considerable care. Mathematics and philosophy share the task of ensuring that the concepts are properly formulated, that they are clearly understood. On the other hand, the distinction between the two subjects may be summarized by the observation that philosophy works with natural language, with words, whereas mathematics works objectively, with symbols. Sciences such as physics, chemistry, biology, economics and sociology begin with verbal formulations, and then move progressively towards symbolic codifications. As this move takes place, mathematics inherits from philosophy the job of validating the science’s concepts and arguments (while philosophy may then assume the job of interpreting the increasingly refined science in “layman’s terms”, in natural language). One special benefit that mathematics has to offer is its universality: a single mathematical model may be capable of describing a wide range of phenomena by means of varying interpretations of the symbols used. The current paper presents a striking example The canonical ensemble model, originally developed in the context of equilibrium statistical mechanics to describe a system that has cooled to an ultimate state of maximal entropy, may be reinterpreted to describe the evolution of a non-equilibrium system away from a state of maximal entropy and towards an ultimate state of certainty. Examples like this are salutary reminders of the need for the precision and clarity that mathematics and philosophy can bring.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Birkhoff, G., 1967, Lattice Theory, Providence, R.I., American Mathematical Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, D.R.; Wiley, E.O., 1986 (1st ed.), Evolution as Entropy: Towards a Unified Theory of Biology, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenfest, P.; Ehrenfest, T., 1907, Über zwei bekannte Einwände gegen das Boltzmannsche H-Theorem, Phys. Zeit, vol. 8, pp. 311–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eigen, M., 1971, Self-organization of matter and the evolution of biological macromolecules, Die Naturwissenschaften, vol. 58, pp. 465–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin-Löf, P., 1966, The definition of random sequences, Information and Control, vol. 9, pp. 602–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patten, B., 1982, Environs: relativistic elementary particles for ecology, Am. Nat., vol. 119, pp. 179–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I.; George, C., 1983, The Second Law as a selection principle, the microscopic theory of dissipative processes in quantum systems, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci., vol. 80, pp. 4590–4594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smoluchowski, M.V., 1915, Molekulartheoretische Studien über Umkehr thermodynamisch irreversible Vorgänge und über Wiederkehr abnormaler Zustände, Wien. Ber., vol. 124, pp. 339–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, C.J.; McBride, J.L., 1974, On Eigen’s theory of the self-organization of matter and the evolution of biological macromolecules, Math. Biosci., vol. 21, pp. 127–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uspenskii, V.A.; Semonov, A.L., Kishen, A., 1990, Can an individual sequence of zeros and ones be random?, Russian Mathematical Surveys, vol. 45, pp. 121–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Smith, J.D.H. (1998). Canonical Ensembles, Evolution of Competing Species, and the Arrow of Time. In: van de Vijver, G., Salthe, S.N., Delpos, M. (eds) Evolutionary Systems. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1510-2_12

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1510-2_12

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5103-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1510-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics