Skip to main content

The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science

  • Chapter
E.A. Burtt, Historian and Philosopher

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 226))

Abstract

The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science is the first historical account of the scientific revolution.1 In this book Burtt placed Newton within a context of culture and religion without devaluing his scientific achievement. But, in a surprising way, the Newtonian world-view is thrown into new light. Burtt claims that the mechanical universe with its Cartesian underpinning, that is, the duality of subject and object, and the mathematization of nature, culminating in “laws of nature,” is just “he objectification of the mood of an age, fitful and temporary”. Furthermore, scientific claims to truth come at the expense of other means of human knowing which we can not afford to lose. Although the book might be read simply as a polemic against logical positivism, which was competing with pragmatism in the U.S. in the 1920s, it should also be considered as a demonstration of a new philosophy of science. In The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science Burtt is saying that science is a culturally conditioned expression of human experience, just one way of knowing among many, and that scientific truth is a changing truth.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. H. Floris Cohen has given the best account and critique of E.A. Burtt and The Metaphysical Foundations in print today in his The Scientific Revolution, An Historiographical Inquiry,(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994). Cohen is the first to acknowledge the significance of Burtt’s “radical historical critique,” where others have missed it. Cohen is liberal with his credit to Burtt as “the first to adopt a ‘relative discontinuity’ position” to explain how scientific knowledge is acquired (96, 149) and as “at the head of an array of historians to the Scientific Revolution who, in the sixties, began to look upon this signal event in European intellectual history as having brought, besides impressive gains in our knowledge, some no less consequential losses” (96–97). Although Cohen acknowledges that it is Alexandre Koyré who is at the center of the historiographical “treasure” that the Scientific Revolution has become, he makes it clear that Koyré’s priority in this treasure is a debt he owed to Burtt (101). Most important of all, Cohen did not miss the fact that Burtt’s work has been a powerful influence in “the debate over the rationality of early modern science.” He rightly points out the wide-ranging impact of Burtt’s work on T.S. Kuhn and Frances Yates (111, 179–182) and sums up this way: “Lonely Burtt’s account is still very relevant to the course of present-day discussions of the Scientific Revolution. And what is even more: It is from Burtt’s book that Koyré’s concept of the Scientific Revolution probably found its origin” (89).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Burtt, Two Basic Issues In the Problem of Meaning and Truth in Essays in Honor of John Dewey on the occasion of his seventieth birthday, October 20, 1929, ( New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1929 ), 69.

    Google Scholar 

  3. R.G. Collingwood, Essay on Metaphysics, (Oxford, England: The Clarendon Press, 1940 ).

    Google Scholar 

  4. The term Burtt used here was used both by John Dewey in his Reconstruction in Philosophy and by the Phenomenologists who borrowed it from Francis Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Metaphysical Foundations,229.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., 229.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., 229.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., 229.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., 228.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., 228.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., 228.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., 228–229.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., 227–228.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Metaphysical Foundations,227.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Elaine Daston in Isis,1994.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Burtt’s historical approach earned him the misnomer, Hegelian, but at no time in his long career did Burtt ever believe that there was an Absolute and True Reality or Being qua Being which man could know. His preference for the genetic method led him to a Collingwood brand of historicism and his interest in religion invited the inaccurate conclusion that he was a “true believer.” He was agnostic about the nature and even the existence of the traditional God of Christianity until the last years of his life.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Burtt, The English Philosophers from Bacon to Mill,(New York: The Modern Library, 1939), xi–xii.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The Metaphysical Foundations,208.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Quoted from Bertrand Russell, A Free Man’s Worship in Mysticism and Logic (New York, 1918) Metaphysical Foundations,23.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Russell, A Free Man’s Worship in Philosophical Essays, (New York, Bombay, and Calcutta: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1910 ), 61.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  22. John H. Randall, The Making of the Modern Mind, ( Boston, New York, etc.: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1926 ), 637.

    Google Scholar 

  23. John H. Randall, The Making of the Modern Mind,638.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Even further background can be gained on the impact of science during the last of the nineteenth and the early part of the twentieth centuries in Randall’s Philosophy After Darwin Chapters for The Career of Philosophy Volume III and Other Essays, edited by Beth Singer, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1977). See the first three chapters, especially, Chapter 1, The Conflict of the Religious Tradition With Science and page 29 where Randall discusses Bertrand Russell’s A Free Man’s Worship and what Russell’s essay meant to the young radicals around Columbia University in the 1920s.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Bertrand Russell, Two Dogmas of Naturalism,a review of The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science by E.A. Burtt in Dial 79 (September, 1925): 255–258.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Russell, History of Western Philosophy and it Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest Times to the Present Day,(London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd., first published in 1946). New edition (reset), 1961 is cited here, pages 514515.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., 210.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., 212.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., 214.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., 212.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., 230.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., 218. Quoted from Newton’s Principles,II, 314. Burtt’s further notation is: Cf. also Opticks,380.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Quoted from Newton’s Principles,II, 160 in Ibid., 218–219.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Metaphysical Foundations,229.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., 229.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See James E. Force, Newton’s Sleeping Argument and the Newtonian Synthesis of Science and Religion in Standing on the Shoulders of Giants, A longer View of Newton and Halley. Essays Commemorating the 1985–1986 Return of Comet Halley,edited by Norman J.W. Thrower, (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990), page 125 and Force, Hume’s Interest in Newton and Science in Essays on the Context, Nature, and Influence of Isaac Newton’s Theology,edited by James E. Force and Richard H. Poplin, (Dordrecth, Boston and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1990), 181–206; see especially page 199, footnote 30. Force explains how his interpretation of Newton relies on Burtt. Force has taken Burtt’s reading of Newton and Hume, which involves Burtt’s own undeclared use of Hume’s brand of radical skepticism turned back on Hume to give what Force wants to see as Hume’s reading of Newton. It is Burtt’s reading of Hume and Burtt’s reading of Newton which Force takes as Hume’s critique of Newton.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Force, Newton’s Sleeping Argument and the Newtonian Synthesis of Science and Religion,125.

    Google Scholar 

  38. David Hume, Concerning Natural Religion Part II in The English Philosophers from Bacon to Mill,edited and with an Introduction by E.A. Burtt, (New York: Modern Library, Random House, 1939), 699–708 and Part XII, 753–755.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Metaphysical Foundations,300.

    Google Scholar 

  40. H. Floris Cohen, 92.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Villemaire, D.D. (2002). The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science. In: E.A. Burtt, Historian and Philosopher. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 226. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1331-3_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1331-3_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5937-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1331-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics