Skip to main content

Selected Earlier Work on the Syntax and Semantics of Focusing Particles

  • Chapter
Directionality and Logical Form

Part of the book series: Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory ((SNLT,volume 34))

  • 84 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter will give an overview and critical evaluation of selected work on constructions which involve focusing particles such as English only and even. These constructions have presented a challenge to linguistic theory for as long as the field of formal linguistics exists. The intricacies of these elements stem from the fact that they merge syntactic, semantic and phonological properties in such a way that all three components make almost equal contributions in accounting for the observed patterns. In the short history of formal linguistics, elements like only, even, also etc. have received attention mainly from a semantic point of view. Besides older generative work like Anderson’s (1972) and Fraser’s (1971) work on even, part of Jackendoff (1972) and Ross and Cooper (1979), much work was carried out in semantics and in the Montague Grammar tradition. I want to mention here Karttunen and Peters (1979). As for the description of English, influential developments came from Fauconnier, Karttunen and Peters and more recently from the dissertation of Mats Rooth (Rooth, 1985) to which we will turn in detail below. An excellent presentation of English data is given in Taglicht (1984). Some of Taglicht’s observations have direct influence on the theory of Logical Form. With respect to German, I want to mention the groundbreaking work by Hans Altmann, Altmann (1976; 1978) and, with a more theoretical orientation, Jacobs (1983) to which we will also turn in detail. Numerous articles have been published on individual particles of this type exploring mainly their semantic, pragmatic and communicative aspects. An in-depth analysis of the semantics and pragmatics of a single German particle is, for instance, given in Lerner and Zimmermann’s (1981) study of nur.1 Instead of giving a broad review of the work that has been done in the past, I will confine myself in this chapter to a review of Jacobs (1983) and Rooth (1985), as most of the descriptive as well as theoretical development is condensed in these two contributions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Lerner and Zimmermann were, however, not interested in the syntax of nur. For this reason, their work is not quite central for my present purposes.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For discussion see Bayer (1993) and Müller (1993: ch.7); for alternatives see Frey and Tappe (1992), Fanselow (1992) and Haider (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Bhatt (1990), Löbel (1990), and Olsen (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Since it is normally assumed that main clauses are CPs in German, I use an IP embedded under C’.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See also Reuland and Kosmeijer (1988) and Bayer and Kornfilt (1990; 1994) for relevant discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Notice that functional heads like D and C are virtually free morphemes that can bear phonetic prominence, engage in coordination etc., while I has none of these properties.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Roughly everything but it or German es.

    Google Scholar 

  8. C-command is to be understood in the sense of “first branching node up”.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Klima (1964) and Rizzi (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Jacobs (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  11. I will always mark focus with capitals.

    Google Scholar 

  12. The Nuclear Stress Rule of English makes it hard to decide whether only focuses on the entire VP or on the rightmost DP, unless the DP receives extra heavy stress. To make the point clearer, one can look at examples such as

    Google Scholar 

  13. i) John will [only [introduce BILL to Mary]] where focus remains on Bill and cannot spread to VP. On the relation between the phonology of focusing and its correlates in syntax and semantics, see Bierwisch (1966), Höhle (1982), Culicover and Rochemont (1983), Selkirk (1984), Gussenhoven (1984), von Stechow and Ullmann (1986) and Rochemont (1986) among others.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Tancredi (1990) calls this the Principle of Lexical Association (PLA)

    Google Scholar 

  15. i) Principle of Lexical AssociationAn operator like only must be associated with a lexical constituent in its c-command domain The PLA rests on the observation that the trace seen in (iib) cannot serve as an associate of only:

    Google Scholar 

  16. ii) a. He only likes MARY

    Google Scholar 

  17. b. MARY, he only likes e

    Google Scholar 

  18. Notice, however, that the PLA cannot be at work universally. In German V2-clauses, for instance, it is possible that nur associates with the finite verb which has moved to the C-position:

    Google Scholar 

  19. iii) Martina TANZT vermutlich nur mit Hans-Dietrich Martina dances presumably only with Hans-Dietrich

    Google Scholar 

  20. Presumably Martina only DANCES with Hans-Dietrich (… but does not go to bed with him) There seems to be one serious exception to (18a). As has sometimes been observed, even but not only may escape the (surface) c-command requirement:

    Google Scholar 

  21. vi) JOHN would even/?*only understand Syntactic Structures

    Google Scholar 

  22. Of course, it is not unproblematic at all when we follow the usual GB-assumption that in German CP is extraposed in the sense of adjunction to IP. In this case, nur would cease to c-command CP. We will turn to this problem in detail in chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  23. It is sometimes claimed that a DP with an attached particle cannot appear in an English PP either; (see, for instance, Taglicht, 1984 ). The construction may be marked, but it should not be taken to be ungrammatical. (i) shows a real example (taken from Davison, 1988: 187) whose direct translation into

    Google Scholar 

  24. i) It has scope over only the matrix-clause element it binds… i) *Es hat über nur das Matrixsatz-Element Skopus, das es bindet… We will turn to this issue in more detail in chapters 2 and 3.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The judgements are my own. Speakers of German sometimes show a slight disagreement in their judgements. It is clear, however, that the b-sentences are far less acceptable than the a-examples.

    Google Scholar 

  26. In the present work I will not deal with these problems of coordination. See Bayer (1990a) for some discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See König (1991: ch.5).

    Google Scholar 

  28. See König (1991: ch.4).

    Google Scholar 

  29. We will turn to necessary exceptions below.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See Montague (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  31. In briefly mentioning representations such as (45) as “GB-style”, v. Stechow (1991a) seems to assume that they can be properly interpreted. Rooth provides a footnote in which he refers to an idea by David Pesetsky’s suggesting that cases of multiple foci may be treated along the lines of multiple occurrences of Wh. In this case, however, it is assumed that one Wh-element is in a designated operator position (SpecCP) while those in situ adjoin to it in LF. The index of the syntactically moved element binds its variable in LF, but the index of the adjoined Wh-elements does not. Exactly this leads to the well-known ECP-explanation of superiority effects in English (see Chomsky, 1981). On this background it is unclear how two elements which are both moved in LF could undergo absorption. The first question would be what will absorb what; the second, why there are no superiority type asymmetries (including ungrammatical cases).

    Google Scholar 

  32. As the treatment of focus in generative syntax has shown, it is likewise not unproblematic to take it as a quasi-quantifier phrase that undergoes LF-movement. (See Rooth’s discussion of Chomsky, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Of course, one would like to know why QR should be confined to DPs. (54b) could be seen as a quantified VP which could equally be affected by QR. This would render the example ambiguous too. We will return to scope fixing effects later on and show why this undesirable possibility cannot arise.

    Google Scholar 

  34. According to Steve Berman and others it is, for example, possible to say (59a) in a context like I only invited ANN to the party because she is a LINGUIST, but I didn’t invite SUSAN because she is a SINGER. According to Regine Eckardt (p.c.) reason adverbials are hard to get because reasons can be too manifold to mentally invoke constrained enough alternatives.

    Google Scholar 

  35. These examples become grammatical when there is a possible parse that isolates the material that must undergo movement; at least for German there seems to be a parse in which the verb has moved out of a VP that may contain the subject:

    Google Scholar 

  36. i) Mehr Opert liebhaber schlugen vor, daß Domingo den “Tristan” in WIEN singen sollte, als Pavarotti den “Lohengrin” in Salzburg

    Google Scholar 

  37. Krifka (1992: 23) assumes a “one-to-one mapping between focus operators and foci” and takes cases of multiple foci as semantic correspondents of a list of more than one variable that can be bound by a lambda operator.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1996 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bayer, J. (1996). Selected Earlier Work on the Syntax and Semantics of Focusing Particles. In: Directionality and Logical Form. Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, vol 34. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1272-9_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1272-9_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4623-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1272-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics