Skip to main content

‘Mathesis Universalis’ in the Sixteenth Century

  • Chapter
Descartes’s Mathematical Thought

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 237))

  • 1249 Accesses

Abstract

It was through Proclus’s Commentary on the First Book of Euclids Elements, among others, that a novel mathematical idea entered the intellectual world of the sixteenth century. It is not too much to say that there has been no impact greater than Proclus regarding the status of mathematical sciences among the philosophies of mathematics in early modern Europe. We have seen in Chapter 2, § 2 that Clavius was greatly inspired by Proclus’s philosophy of mathematics. By attempting to graft, as it were, the mathematical thought of Proclus on the trunk of the scholastic-Aristotelian scheme of learning, the Jesuit mathematician promoted the study of mathematics. Descartes is conjectured to have acquired the thought of Proclus through Clavius or others. Proclus also played a crucial role in spreading the idea that there is a substantial mathematical discipline prior and superior to arithmetic and geometry. This idea was useful to convince thinkers of the sixteenth century that there existed a mathematical discipline of ‘mathesis universalis’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Procli Diadochi in primum Euclidis Elementorum librum commentari, ed. G. Friedlein (Leipzig, 1873), p. 7, 11. 17–18; Prodi Diadochi Lycii in primum Euclidis Elementorum cornmentariorum libri IV, a Francisco Barocio (Padua, 1560), p. 4. Note that in the Greek original the word “commentary” was not used: Eiç Tò TpDTOv TDV Evkaeläov UTOLXEIWV QLPiov. As for the English translation, we basically follow G. R. Morrow’s translation: Proclus, A Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements (Ch. 5, n. 180). His translation of the words for `common mathematics’ is not necessarily careful and consistent. Therefore, our translation sometimes deviates from it without notice. Morrow has included Friedlein’s pagination, hence we do not indicate the pages of his translation. We also refer to Paul Ver Eecke’s French translation: Proclus de Lycie, Les Commentaires sur le premier livre des Éléments d’Euclide, traduits par Paul Ver Eecke (Bruges, 1948).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Barozzi, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Friedlein, p. 18, 1. 16; Barozzi, p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Friedlein, p. 44, ll. 2–3; Barozzi, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Friedlein, pp. 43–44.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Friedlein, p. 5; Barozzi, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Friedlein, pp. 7–8; Barozzi, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Friedlein, p. 8; Barozzi, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Friedlein, pp. 8–9; Barozzi, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Friedlein, p. 13; Barozzi, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For the concept of `projectionism’ as opposed to `abstractionism’, see Ian Mueller, “Forward to the 1992 Edition,” Morrow’s English translation (n. 1), p. xxvi. See also Idem, “Mathematics and Philosophy in Proclus’ Commentary on Book I of Euclid’s Elements, in Proclus: Lecteur et interprète des ancients, publiées par Jean Pépin et H. D. Saffrey (Paris, 1987), pp. 305–318, esp. p. 317; Idem, “Aristotle’s Doctrine of Abstractionism in the Commentators,” in Aristotle Transformed (Ch. 6, n. 24), pp. 463–480, esp. p. 473.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Friedlein, p. 9; Barozzi, p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Friedlein, pp. 42–43; Barozzi, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Friedlein, p. 44; Barozzi, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Friedlein, p. 18; Barozzi, p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Plato, The Republic, translated with an introduction by Desmond Lee (London, 21974). We indicate the Stephanus pagination only.

    Google Scholar 

  17. As for the relationship between mathematics and dialectic in Plato’s thought, see F. M. Cornford, “Mathematics and Dialectic in the Republic VI.—VII.,” Mind, XLI (1932), pp. 3752 and 173–190; Julia Annas, An Introduction to Plato’s Republic (Oxford, 1981), Chapter II, “Philosophy and Mathematics,” pp. 272–293. On Plato’s mathematical thought in general, see Harold Cherniss, “Plato as Mathematician,” The Review of Metaphysics, 4 (1951), pp. 395425.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See I. Mueller, “Forward to the 1992 Edition” (n. 1), p. xxix. Mueller uses “universal mathematics” deliberately for our “common mathematics.” This use is, I think, legitimate.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Aristotle states in Book I of Topics (101a37–101b4): “It [the treatise] is a further use in relation to the principles used in the several sciences. For it is impossible to discuss them at all from the principles proper to the particular science in hand, seeing that the principles are primitive in relation to everything else: it is through reputable opinions about them that these have to be discussed, and this task belongs properly, or most appropriately, to dialectic; for dialectic is a process of criticism wherein lies the path to the principles of all inquiries.” For Plato’s influence on Aristotle, see H. D. P. Lee, “Geometrical Method and Aristotle’s Account of First Principles,” The Classical Quarterly, XXIX (1935), pp. 113–124, esp. pp. 119–124.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See J. D. G. Evans, Aristotle’s Concept of Dialectic (Cambridge, 1977), esp. “Summary: Aristotle and Plato on Dialectic and Science,” pp. 49–52. “Aristotle preserves the Platonic idea of dialectic as unrestricted in its scope. On the other hand this lack of restriction is for Aristotle an indication of the unscientific character of dialectic, whereas for Plato it had been an indication that dialectic was the only true science.” (p. 50.) Similarities and dissimilarities in general between Plato’s and Aristotle’s philosophy are discussed by G. E. L. Owen in his excellent paper “The Platonism of Aristotle,” in Logic, Science and Dialectic: Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy, ed. Martha Nussbaum (Ithaca, 1986), pp. 200–220. On mathematics and dialectic, consult especially pp. 211–216.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Arpkd Szabó, Anfänge der Griechischen Mathematik (Munchen/Wien, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Simon Grynaeus’s “Praefatio” to his Greek editio princeps of Euclid’s Elements (n. Ch. 2, n. 51). An interesting discussion can be seen in E. Kessler, “Clavius entre Proclus et Descartes” (Ch. 2, n. 16), pp. 290–294. Cf. H. Schilling, Die Geschichte der axiomatischen Methode im 16. and beginnenden 17. Jahrhundert (Hildesheim, 1969), p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Stanislas Breton, Philosophie et mathématique chez Proclus (Paris, 1969), p. 89; Annick Charles-Saget, L’Architecture du divin: Mathématique et philosophie chez Plotin et Proclus (Paris, 1982), pp. 195, 205, and 295. On the other hand, Nicolai Hartmann doesn’s seem to see the concept of `mathesis universalis’ in Proclus’s Commentary, for, according to him even the theory of proportion is not common to both geometry and arithmetic. Nicolai Hartmann, Des Proklus Diadochus philosophische Anfangsgründe der Mathematik nach den ersten zwei Büchern des Euklidkommentars (Gießen, 1909), p. 15: “Die Geometrie stellt den Grundsatz der Proportion für dei Größen, die Arithmetik für die Zahlen auf, jede aus ihren eigenen Mitteln und für ihre eigenen Zwecke.” Cf. Geneviève de Pesloüan’s French translation in Breton, Ibid., p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  24. lamblichus, De communi mathematica scientia liber, ed. Nicolaus Festa (Stuttgart, 1975). The content of this treatise is analyzed in Dominic J. O’Meara, Pythagoras Revived: Mathematics and Philosophy in Late Antiquity (Oxford, 1989), 4. “Pythagorean Mathematical Science (Book III: On General Mathematical Science), pp. 44–51. Cf. Descartes, Règles utiles et claires etc., éd. par J.-L. Marion et P. Costabel (La Haye, 1977), p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See Ian Mueller, “Iamblichus and Proclus’ Euclid Commentary,” Hermes, Bd. 115 (1987), pp. 334–348; O’Meara, Op. cit. (n. 24), pp. 157–166; Morrow, Op. cit. (n. 1), p. 345.

    Google Scholar 

  26. O’Meara, Op. cit. (n. 24), p. 121.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Roger Bacon, Communia mathematica: Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi, Fasc. XVI, ed. Robert Steele (Oxford, 1940), p. 38: “Et hec pars Mathematice non debet vocari Geometria nec Arithmetica nec Astrologia nec Astronomia nec Musica, sed de elementis et de radicibus totius Mathematice que debent premitti ante partes speciales.” On the date of the composition, see A. C. Crombie and J. D. North, “Bacon, Roger,” DSB, I, p. 378.

    Google Scholar 

  28. R. Bacon, Op. cit., p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  29. The `Opus Majus’ of Roger Bacon, ed. by John Henry Briges (Frankfurt/Main, 1964), p. 103: “[…] virtus tota logicae dependet ex mathematica.” Cf. The Opus Majus of Roger Bacon, A Translation by Robert Belle Burke, Vol. 1 (New York, 1962), p. 120

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 106: “[…] in sola mathematica sunt demonstrationes potissimae propter per causam necessariam.” Cf. Burke’s translation, p. 124. See also Communia mathematica, p. 15: “[…] cum sola mathematica sit vere demonstrativa secundum demonstrationem potissimam

    Google Scholar 

  31. Communia mathematica, p. 63: “Methaphysica est prior mathematica et magis abstracta

    Google Scholar 

  32. Johannes Kepler, Gesammelte Werke, Bd. VI: Harmonise mundi (München, 1940). In “Personenregister” “Proklus” appears 34 times.

    Google Scholar 

  33. A. Crapulli, Mathesis universalis (Roma, 1969), p. 146. The quoted Latin passage is as follows (A. Romanus, Apologia pro Archimede, pp. 22–23): “Geometriae and Arithmeticae communem esse scientiam, gum quantitatem generaliter vti mensurabilem considerat […] ad quam spectarent affectiones communes omnibus quantitatibus […] non abstractis tantum vt numeris and magnitudinibus, sed concretis etiam, vti temporibus, sonis, vocibus, locis, motibus, potentiis […] propositiones eas quæ spectant ad analogias […] ad scientiam aliquam vniuersalem iure merito pertinere existimandum est.” We have referred to Van Roomen’s original rather than what Crapulli cited.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See in detail Crapulli, p. 150.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Piccolomini, Op. cit. (Ch. 2, n. 18), f. LXXXXVIIv: “cuiusdam facultas communis ad Geometriam, and Arithmeticam.”

    Google Scholar 

  36. Dasypodius, Analyseis Geometricee sex librorum Euclidis (Argentinensi, 1566), f. LXXXVIv: “[S]unt etiam quæ cum sint communia ex geometria in arithmeticam: et ex hac in illam transferuntur: uel etiam utrinque se habent: et peræque in geometria, atque in arithmetica considerantur: imo in cæteris quoque disciplinis adhiberi possunt: quia ex illa uniuersali µaBr)µareni) desumuntur: ut sunt ?vaaaaryal,aal AvavTpocpaì T(DI/ Aory’uiv: Q4Jv0É’QELç,bcacp€vECç et quæ huius sunt generis.”

    Google Scholar 

  37. /bid., f. XCVIIr: “His quintus liber peculiarem dectrinam instituit de proportionibus: qu diffusæ sunt per uniuersam rerum naturam, non ad geometriam tantum aut arithmeti-cam pertinent, sed ad alias scientias atque idcirco potius referri debet, ad uniuersalem illam disciplinam mathematicam, qu reliquas omnes tanquam species sub se comprehendit.”

    Google Scholar 

  38. Benedictus Pererius, De Cornmunibus omnium rerum naturalium principijs f4 affectionibus, libri gvindecim (Rome, 1576), p. 34: “Quaemadmodum non est dubium quin sit aliqua scientia Mathematica communis, quae debeat speculari affectiones communes magnitudini and numero, quae tamen scientia, à Mathematicis non numeratur distincta à Geometria and Arithmetica.” Crapulli mistakenly refers to this statement on p. 37 instead of p. 34. See Crapulli, p. 95. Notice that Pereira admitted `scientia Mathematica communis’ while still claiming that “the mathematical doctrine is not properly a science” (dottrina Mathematica non est propriè scientia) (Pereira, p. 24).

    Google Scholar 

  39. A. Romanus, Apologia, p. 23. See our discussion on pp. 354–356.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Crapulli, pp. 125–143.

    Google Scholar 

  41. A. Romanus, Apologia, p. 23. Cf. Philippe Gilbert, “Les sciences exactes dans l’ancienne université de Louvain,” Revue des questions scientifiques, XVI (1884), pp. 438–453, esp. p. 449. Figure 7.1 shows the Latin original. The Komaba Library of the University of Tokyo possesses a copy of this rare book.

    Google Scholar 

  42. This is the point Crapulli emphasizes. See Crapulli, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  43. H. L. L. Busard, “Roomen, Adriaan van,” DSB,XI, p. 532.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Romanus, Vniversee mathesis idea (Würzburg, 1602), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  45. /bid.,pp. 6–7: “Demonstrationes Mathematica an sint potissimæ, apud nonnullos controversum est; Benedictus Pererius sentit potissimas non esse, cùm non progrediantur ex principijs, qva sint causa conclusionis, uti pluribus ostendit exemplis ex elementis Geometri-cis Euclidis desumptis. Verùm qvicqvid sit, (hoc est sive potissimæ sint, sive non) hoc unum indubitatum est apud omnes, demonstrationes mathematicas esse certissimas inter omnes demonstrationes qvarumcumqve facultatum. In rebus sanè naturalibus and sensibilibus dicere ferè semper cogimur (Aristotele teste) hoc vel illud fieri 2ç Éirì 7roÀv, vel etiam g àv µr1.p roöI(et; at contrà (2. Metaphys. 3) Mathematicarum scientiarum summa est certitudo excedens omnem aliarum facultatum certitudinem.” Pererius, Op. cit. (n. 38), Lib. I, Cap. XII, “Scientia speculativam non dici vniuovè de Mathematicis disciplinis and alijs, quoniam doctrina Mathematica non est propriè scientia,” pp. 24–26. Aristotle’s statement in the Metaphysics, II, 3 (995a14–17) can be seen in Ch. 2, n. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  46. /bid., p. 8: “Vnde à Metaphysica superatur, Physicam verò superat.”

    Google Scholar 

  47. /bid., p. 12: “Metaphysicae non modo vtilis sed and necessaria videtur.” Van Roomen continues to state the reason: “For the entrance to metaphysics opens to nobody but through the mathematical disciplines. Certainly if we should try to raise the power and sharpenness of our intellect without any mediation from sensible things, which the physicist considers, to things divided and separated from every sensible matter, which the metaphysician contemplates, we ourselves will be made blind just as it happens to one who is sent out of a certain dark cave in which he has been hidden long into the clearest light of the sun. And for this reason, before the intellect ascends from physical things, to which matter subjected to senses is joined, to metaphysical things, which are separated greatly from matter, in order not to be filled with the brightness of the latter it is necessary, earlier than that, to be accustomed with less abstract things as are considered by mathematicians in order that one can comprehend them easier. And therefore the Divine Plato rightly maintains that the mathematical disciplines raise the soul to the contemplation of divine things and sharpen the mind.” (p. 12.) “Nulli etenim ad Metaphysicam pater aditus, nisi per mathematicas disciplinas. Nam si à rebus sensibilibus, qvas Physicus considerat, ad res ab omni materia sensibili secretas, seiunctasqve qvas contemplatur Metaphysicus, vires, aciemqve nostri intellectus attollere absque ullo medio tentemus: nos metipsos excæcabimus, non secus, ac ei contingit, qvi è carcere aliqvo tenebricoso, in qvo diu latuit, in lucem Solis clarissimam emittitur. Qvamobrem, anteqvam à rebus physicis, qvæ materiæ sensibus obnoxiæ, sunt conjunctæ, ad res metaphysicas, qv æ sunt ab eadem maxime avulsæ, intellectus ascendat; necesse est, ne harum claritate offundatur, prius eum assvefieri rebus minùs abstractis, qvales à Mathematicis considerantur, ut faciliùs illas possit comprehendere. Qvocirca rectè Divinus Plato mathematicas disciplinas erigere animum, ad divinarum rerum contemplationum exacuere mentis aciem affirmat.”

    Google Scholar 

  48. Romanus, Ibid., p. 16: “Vniuersalis continet elementa motus violenti; diciturqve propriè Mechanica, Pappo Manganaria.” The term `Manganaria’ is used in Pappus’s Collection, VIII: “7) TÉxv71 T Jv µaryryavaplwv” (Hultsch, III, p. 1024, I. 14); “ars manganorum” (Commandino, f. 305v); “l’art des artificiers” (Ver Eecke, II, p. 810). Incidentally, Van Roomen wrote the title of Chapter XVI as “De Manganaria sive mechanaria proprie dicta,” probably by mistake. “Mechanaria” should be corrected to “mechanica”, of course.

    Google Scholar 

  49. P. 56: “Evthymetria est scientia quæ per radios visuales aptè directos, lineas rectas finitas metitur.”

    Google Scholar 

  50. See Heath, A History of Greek Mathematics, Vol. 1, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  51. P 17: “Svpputatrix Grzecis aoryuvruci dicta, est quæ beneficio canonum universalium, ex datis numeris rebus accommodatis quæsitum elicit.”

    Google Scholar 

  52. P. 17: “Posset non incommodè si vox recepta esset Arithmopraxia vocari. Supputatricem hanc à reliquis Mathematicis scientijs separare placuit, quod ea non peculiaris obietti tradat proprietates, verùm omnem numerum respiciat concretum; hoc est, rem quam vis numerabilem sine ulla numerorum proprietate, ita ut omnibus servire queat Matheseos partibus, imò omni ciuili usui. Quodque Logica est in universa Philosophia, idipsum Supputatrix censeri potest in Mathesi.”

    Google Scholar 

  53. /bid “Differt porrò Supputatrix ab Arithmetica, quod h2ec numerorum exhibeat proprietates demonstratione confirmatas, ilia verò sine ulla demonstratione, sine ulla numerorum proprietate, canones paucissimos exhibeat inveniendi and iudicandi, eosque generalissimos longè à Theorematibus and Problematibus Arithmetic2e diversos.”

    Google Scholar 

  54. P. 18: “Principia præter terminorum scienti propriorum explicationem vis habet alia; usus tarnen supputatricis requirit cognitionem proprietatum earum rerum quibus numeri applicantur.”

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid “Supputatrix ergo meritò omnibus mathematicis præmitti potest. Nam Supputatrix doceri sine ulla reliquarum Mathematicarum præexistenti cognitione.”

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ramus, Scholae mathematicae (Ch. 5, n. 161), Lib. 2, p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  57. /bid., p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  58. PP. 20–21: “Prima Mathesis est quæ versatur circa quantitatem absolutè sumptam. Objectum eius est Quantitas absolute sumpta. Finis verb, affectiones quantitatibus omnibus communes exhibere. Principia habet tantum propria. Locum in Mathesi obtinet primum. Eadem ratione qua Prima Philosophia inter reliquas philosophicas scientias prima est.”

    Google Scholar 

  59. P 21: “Hanc scientiam à nemine adhuc descriptam iusto volumine aliquando proponemus. Huius specimen in Apologia nostra proposuimus, at veriorem materiam suppeditant variorum commentarij, quam in ordinem redigere studebimus.”

    Google Scholar 

  60. The first twenty chapters constituting the first part of De principiis ex mathesi desumendis may correspond to the previous Vnivers x mathesis idea. See Henri Bosmans, “Romain (Adrien)” (Ch. 5, n. 189), cols. 879–880.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Romanus, Ibid., p. 22: “Principia habet turn propria, tum ex Prima Mathesi desumpta. Locum in Mathesi post primam, obtinet primum.”

    Google Scholar 

  62. ee “Principia praeter propria, etiam desumit, turn ex prima Mathesi, turn ex Arithmetic”.“ (p. 23) and ”Proximum in Mathesi locum post Arithmeticam obtinet.“ (p. 24)

    Google Scholar 

  63. Crapulli, p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  64. B. Pererius, Op. cit. (n. 38), pp. 24–27. See also Crapulli, IV. “La `scientia mathematica communis’ in analogia alla `prima philosophia’ secondo B. Pereira,” pp. 93–99; G. C. Giacobbe, Op. cit. (Ch. 2, n. 29).

    Google Scholar 

  65. André Robinet, Aux Sources de l’esprit cartésien: L’Axe la Ramée-Descartes de la Dialectique de 1555 aux Regulae (Paris, 1996) and Idem, “L’Axe La Ramée-Descartes: Position dans la Règle IV de la ((Mathesis universalis)),” Descartes et la Renaissance: Actes du Colloque internationale de Tours des 22–24 mars 1996, Réunis par Emmanuel Faye (Paris, 1999), pp. 67–76.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Crapulli, Op. cit., VII. “Conclusioni sulla mathesis universalis nel sec. XVI,” pp. 145–154.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Alfred W. Crosby, The Measure of Reality: Quantification and Western Society, 12501600 (Cambridge, 1997). On the technical side, see John J. Roche, The Mathematics of Measurement: A Critical History (London, 1998), esp. Chaps. 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ramus, Scholae mathematicae (Ch. 5, n. 161), Book XIII, p. 212. See my article, “The Acceptance of the Theory of Proportion in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries,” Historia Scientiarum,No. 29 (1985), pp. 107–108.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Klein, “Die griechische Logistik etc.” Quellen und Studien, Bd. 3–2 (1936) (Ch. 5, n. 172), pp. 195–235; English translation, pp. 186–224.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sasaki, C. (2003). ‘Mathesis Universalis’ in the Sixteenth Century. In: Descartes’s Mathematical Thought. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 237. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1225-5_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1225-5_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6487-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1225-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics