Skip to main content

Conclusion

Descartes and the Modern Scheme of Learning

  • Chapter
Book cover Descartes’s Mathematical Thought

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 237))

  • 1233 Accesses

Abstract

Descartes was a product of a transitional period which has been usually characterized as an age of ‘general crisis’. He was born during ‘the crisis of the 1590s’ and in France, where the ‘crisis’ was particularly deep. It is reported that in 1592, four years before he was born, a Spanish writer declared: “England without God, Germany in schism, Flanders in rebellion, France with all these together.”1 In fact, France in the latter half of the sixteenth century suffered successive brutal religious wars up to 1598, the year in which the Edict of Nantes was promulgated by Henri IV, a king newly converted to Catholicism. And it was at a Jesuit college which Henri IV had the Jesuits establish that Descartes was educated. Descartes’s later career was marked by the Thirty Years’ War, which continued from 1618 to 1648. The period of the Thirty Years’ War is characterized as an age of the decline of the Catholic states of Spain and of the rise of the Protestant states of England and the Netherlands, which began to sweep over the seas of the world. The beginning part of the “General Introduction” by the editor of The New Cambridge Modern History, a collection of essays discussing this age synthetically, characterizes this period: “Undeniably the first half of the seventeenth century in Europe (or for that matter in China and to a lesser extent India) was an eventful period, full of conflicts.”2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Quoted in Peter Clark, ed., The European Crisis of the 1590s: Essays in Comparative History (London, 1985), “Introduction,” p. 4. The Spaniard’s name is Mario Antonio de Camos.

    Google Scholar 

  2. n the historical context of Descartes’s lifetime, see, among others, J. P. Cooper, ed., The New Cambridge Modern History, Vol. 4: The Decline of Spain and the Thirty Years War 1609–48/59 (Cambridge, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Henri Gouhier, “La crise de la théologie au temps de Descartes,” Revue de théologie et de philosophie, t. IV (1964), p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Theodore K. Rabb, The Struggle for Stability in Early Modern Europe (New York, 1975), p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  5. bid., p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  6. For the problem of certainty in this period, see, for example, Henry G. van Leeuwen, “Certainty in Seventeenth-Century Thought,” Dictionary of the History of Ideas, ed. by Philip P. Wiener, Vol. 1 (New York, 1973), pp. 304–311.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Desmond M. Clarke, Descartes’ Philosophy of Science (Manchester, 1982), p. 5. The author has emphasized that Descartes was not a dogmatic rationalist but a practical scientist attaching importance to experience.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Richard W. Hadden, On the Shoulders of Merchants: Exchange and the Mathematical Conception of Nature in Early Modern Europe (Albany, 1994).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Natalie Zemon Davis, “Mathematics in the Sixteenth-Century French Academies: Some Further Evidence,” Renaissance News, 11 (1958), p. 9; Eadem, “Sixteenth-Century French Arithmetics on the Business Life,” Journal of the History of Ideas, 21 (1960), p. 36: “The teacher of ‘belles abstractions’ was Ramus’ enemy Jacques Charpentier.” (p. 36, note 58).

    Google Scholar 

  10. W J. Ong, The Presence of the Word: Some Prolegomena for Cultural and Religious History (New Haven, 1967), pp. 63–64. See also the same author’s Ramus, Method and the Decay of Dialogue: From the Art of Discourse to the Art of Reason (Cambridge, Mass., 1958), pp. 307–318.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Leibniz, “Dialogus” (August, 1677), PS, Bd. 7 (Berlin, 1890), p. 191, note; Loemker, p. 185, note 4. This is a note on the margin of the manuscript attached to the sentence: “Try, I pray, whether you can begin any arithmetical calculation without numerical signs.” It is known that Kepler stated a similar sentence.

    Google Scholar 

  12. PS, Bd. 7, p. 125: “ut non jam clamoribus rem agere necesse sit, ad alter alteri dicere possit: calculemus.”

    Google Scholar 

  13. Yvon Bélaval, Leibniz critique de Descartes (Paris, 1960), Chapitre 1 “Intuitionisme et formalisme,” pp. 23–83.

    Google Scholar 

  14. E. Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, Bd. 1: Husserliana, Bd. XVIII (Ch. 8, n. 155), §§ 60–61; Ideen, Bd. 1 (1913): Husserliana, III (1950), §§ 7, 10, & 59; Erste Philosophie (1923/24): Husserliana, VII (1956), pp. 319 & 349; Husserliana, VIII (1959), p. 249. In the last case referred to, Husserl significantly makes an effort to seek “Mathesis univertisalissima” rather than Leibniz’s “Mathesis universalis.”

    Google Scholar 

  15. Husserl, Formale und transzendentale Logik (1929): Husserliana, XVII (1974), p. 84; Formal and Transcendental Logic, translated by Dorian Cairns (The Hague, 1969), p. 80. 16/bid., p. 78; The English translation, p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cartesianische Meditationen, Husserliana, Bd. I (1963), p. 116 (§ 40); Cartesian Meditations, translated by Dorian Cairns (The Hague, 1960), pp. 82–83.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Interestingly one historian of philosophy regards Hilbert as a twentieth-century inheritor of the concept of ‘mathesis universalis’. See Alexander S. Kohanski, The Greek Mode of Thought in Modern Philosophy (Rutherford/Madison/Teaneck, 1984), 36. “DescartesMathesis Universalis,” pp. 124–135, esp. pp. 128–129.

    Google Scholar 

  18. David Hilbert, “Neubegründung der Mathematik. Erste Mitteilung,” Gesammelte Abhandlungen, Bd. III (Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 1970), pp. 157–177. This paper first appeared in Abhandlungen aus dem mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, Bd. 1 (1922), pp. 157–177; “The New Grounding of Mathematics: First Report,” in Paolo Mancosu, ed., From Brouwer to Hilbert: The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s (New York/Oxford, 1998), pp. 198–214.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Kurt Gödel, “Eine metamathematische Resultate uber Entscheidungsdefinitheit und Widerspruchsfreiheit,” Anzeiger der Akademie der Wissenchaft in Wien, Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftliche Klasse, 67 (1930), p. 214; Collected Works, ed. by Solomon Feferman et al., Vol. 1: Publications 1929–1936 (1986), pp. 140–143. See also “Uber formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia mathematica und verwandter Systeme I,” Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38 (1931), pp. 173–193; Collected Works, Vol. 1, pp. 144–195.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Paul Bernays, “Concerning Rationality,” in P. Schilpp, ed., The Philosophy of Karl Popper (1974), pp. 603–605. On competitive theories in mathematics, see Stephan Körner, “On the Relevance of Post-Gödelian Mathematics to Philosophy,” in Imre Lakatos, ed., Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics (Amsterdam, 1967), pp. 118–137, containing discussions with Gert H. Müller and Y. Bar-Hillel. Körner calls for constructing the philosophy of competitive mathematical theories in response to the development of foundational studies, especially since Gödel.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ian Hacking, “Proof and Eternal Truths: Descartes and Leibniz” (Ch. 5, n. 222), pp. 169—

    Google Scholar 

  22. L. E. J. Brouwer, “Intuitionistische Betrachtungen über den Formalismus,” Koninklijke Akademie van Wetenschappen to Amsterdam, Proc. 31 (1928); Collected Works, Vol. 1: Philosophy and Foundations of Mathematics, ed. by A. Heyting (Amsterdam, 1975), p. 410; English translation in Jean van Heijenoort, ed., From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931 (Cambridge, Mass., 1967), p. 491; “Intuitionist Reflections on Formalism,” in Mancosu, Op. cit.(n. 19), p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Poincaré claims that mathematical induction cannot be translated into any merely logical procedure; it becomes a rule proper to mathematics. Thus he states: “We shall always be brought to a full stop—we shall always come to an indemonstrable axiom, which will at bottom be but the position we had to prove translated into another language. We cannot therefore escape the conclusion that the rule of reasoning by recurrence is irreducible to the principle of contradiction.” Poincaré, “On the Nature of Mathematical Reasoning,” in Benacerraf and Putnam, eds., Philosophy of Mathematics (Ch. 8, n. 148), p. 400. Poincaré’s insight was later fully supported by H. Weyl, “Diskussionsbemerkungen zu dem zweiten Hilbertschen Vortrag über die Grundlagen der Mathematik,” Abhandlungen aus dem mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, 6 (1928): Gesammelte Abhandlungen, Bd. III (Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 1968), p. 147; English translation in Van Heijenoort, Op. cit.(n. 23), p. 482.

    Google Scholar 

  24. For the philosophical significance of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, see, among others, Jean Ladrière, Les Limitations internes des formalismes: Étude sur la signification du théorème de Gödel et des théorèmes apparentés dans la théorie des fondements des mathématiques (Louvain/Paris, 1957), Chap. X: “Suggestions philosophiques,” pp. 397–444; Michael Dummett, “The Philosophical Significance of Gödel’s Theorem,” Ratio, 5 (1963), pp. 140–155, & Alain Hazan, “Kurt Gödel, ou le pur formalisme comme Odysée de l’institution mathématique et du subject de la connaissance,” Revue de metaphysique et de morale, 82e année (1977), pp. 88–107.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See Hao Wang, Reflections on Kurt Gödel (Cambridge, Mass./ London, 1987), pp. 50, 80–91, A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass./London, 1996), pp. 69–71. Cf. John W. Dawson, Jr., Logical Dilemmas: The Life and Work of Kurt Gödel (Wellesley, Mass., 1997), pp. 55–59.

    Google Scholar 

  26. L. E. J. Brouwer, “Mathematik, Wissenschaft und Sprache,” Monatshefte far Mathematik und Physik, 36 (1929), pp. 153–164: Collected Works, Vol. 1, pp. 417–428; “Mathematics, Science, and Language,” in Mancosu, Op. cit. (n. 19), pp. 45–53.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Karl Menger, Reminiscences of the Vienna Circle and the Mathematical Colloquium, edited by Louise Golland et al. (Dordrecht/Boston/London, 1994), “Memoires of Kurt Gödel,” p. 223.

    Google Scholar 

  28. I. Lakatos, Proofs and Refutations (Ch. 8, n. 186), esp. Author’s Introduction, pp. 15ldem, “Infinite Regress and Foundations of Mathematics,” in Mathematics, Science and Epistemology: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2 (Cambridge, 1978), pp. 3–23.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Leibniz, “De primae philosophiae Emendatione, et de Notione Substantiae,” PS, Bd. 4, p. 469; Loemker, p. 433.

    Google Scholar 

  30. D. Hilbert, “Die Grundlagen der Mathematik,” Abhandlungen aus dem mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, 6 (1928), pp. 65–85; English translation in Van Heijenoort, Op. cit. (n. 22), pp. 464--479.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Weyl, Op. cit. (n. 24), Gasammelte Abhandlungen, III, pp. 147–149; English translation, pp. 480–484.

    Google Scholar 

  32. H. Putnam, “Mathematics without Foundations,” in Benacerraf and Putnam, eds, Op. cit. (Ch. 8, n. 170), p. 303; Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1 (Cambridge, 21979), p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty, ed. by G. E. M. Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, tr. by Denis Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford, 1969). Fragment number 115.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., Fragment number, 253.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Jules Vuillemin, La Philosophie de l’algèbre, t. 1: Recherches sur quelques concepts et méthodes de l’algèbre moderne (Paris, 1962; 2nd ed. 1993). Unfortunately, a successive volume was not published. The title of its “Conclusion” is significant: “La mathématique universelle,” pp. 465–518. Vuillemin seems to have succeeded Hussearl’s attempt on the philosophy of mathematics, at least in part.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cartesianische Meditationen: Ibid. (n. 17), p. 158; The Engish translation, p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Eugen Fink, VI. Cartesianische Mediationen, Teil 1: Husserliana, Dukurnente,Bd. II/1 (Dordrecht/Boston/London, 1988), pp. 70–71; Sixth Cartesian Meditation: The Idea of a Transcendental Theory of Method, with Textual Notations by Edmund Husserl, translated with an Introduction by Ronald Bruzina (Bloomington/Indianapolis, 191995), p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  38. See, among others, David Carr, Phenomenology and the Problem of History (Evanston, 1974) & Elisabeth Ströker, The Husserlian Foundations of Science (Drodrecht/Boston/London, 1997), Ch. 7: “The Question of History and ”History“ in Husserl’s Intentional Analysis,” pp. 207–227. Ströker states as follows: As early as 1921 he [Husserl] stated—and this is in my knowledge, the first passage of this sort that is “…every ego has its own history and exists only as a subject of history, its own history. And every communicative community of absolute egos, of absolute subjectivities—in full concretion to which belongs the constitution of the world—has its ”passive“ and ”active“ history and exists in this history only. History is the great fact (Faktum) of absolute being; and the final questions…are totally the same with the questions about the absolute sense of history.” (The emphases are by Husserl). The quotation from Husseral is Erste Philosophie (1923/24), Husserliana, VIII, p. 506.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See Stephen Toulmin, Cosmopolis: The Hidden Agenda of Modernity (New York, 1990), pp. 66 & 152–153. See also, Idem, Return to Reason (Cambridge, Mass./London, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  40. A discussion in Elizabeth L. Eisenstein, The Printing Press as an Agent of Change (Cambridge, 1979), esp. pp. 520–566, may be helpful.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Bjorn Engquist and Wilfried Schmid, eds., Mathematics Unlimited-2001 and Beyond, 2 Vols. (Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  42. L. Wittgenstein, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, ed. by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees, and G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford, 1967), p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Janet Abu-Lughod, Before European Hegemony: The World System A. D. 1250--1350 (New York, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Pascal, Œuvere complètes, présentation et notes de Louis Lafumas (Paris, 1963), p. 641: “Feu M. Pascal appelait la philosophie cartésienne le roman de la nature, semble à peu prés à l’histoire de Dom Quichot… (Rapporte par Menjot.)”

    Google Scholar 

  45. Vico, De Antiquissima Italorum Sapientia, Liber primus: Metaphysica (1710), in Opere di G. B. Vico, Vol. 1, ed. Giovanni Gentile e Fausta Nicolini (Bari, 1914), pp. 138–140; Vico, Selected Writings, edited and translated by Leon Pompa (Cambridge, 1982), pp. 56–59.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Vico, De nostri temporis studiorum ratione (1709), Opere, Vol. 1, pp. 87–88; On the Study Methods of Our Time, translated with an Introduction and Notes, by Elio Gianturco (Indianapolis/New York/Kansas City, 1965), pp. 26–30. Vico could have been influenced by his friend Paolo Mattia Doria, an eager advocate of synthetic geometry, and perhaps, by Thomas Hobbes. See David Lachterman, “Vico, Doria e la geometria sintetica,” Bolletino del Centro di Studi Vichiani, X (1980), pp. 10–35.

    Google Scholar 

  47. /bid., p. 85: “[G]eometria demonstramus, quia facimus; si physica demonstrare possemus, faceremus.” See also Gianturco’s translation, p. 23. This Vichian thesis may be difficult to understand. But it will become easier for us to comprehend it if we are reminded of Wittgenstein’s following statements: “The mathematician is an inventor, not a discoverer.” Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, revised edition by G. H. von Wright, R. Rhees and G. E. M. Anscombe (Cambridge, Mass., 1983), p. 99; “[T]he mathematician is a man who builds new roads, or invents new ways of thinking.” Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939, ed. by Cora Diamond (Hassocks, Sussex, 1976), p. 139. On Vico’s statement, see David R. Lachterman, “Mathematics and Nominalism in Vico’s Liber Metaphysicus, in Stephan Otto and Hermut Viechtbauer, eds., Sachkommentar zu Giambattista Vicos Liber Metaphysicus (München, 1985), pp. 47–85. Vico had predecessors on this insight. One of them was Thomas Hobbes. See his Six Lessons to Professors of Mathematics (1656): The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, ed. by William Molesworth, Vol. 7 (London, 1845), pp. 183–184.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Vico, De antiquissima Italorum sapienta (n. 46), p. 147; Pompa’s translation, p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Road Since Structure (Ch. 5, n. 257), pp. 90, 95, & 105–120. Kuhn’s historical approach to philosophy of science is contrasted with ‘logical philosophy of science’ of which a representative philosopher was Carnap. See Donald Gillies, Philosophy of Science in the Twentieth Century: Four Central Themes (Oxford/Cambrige, Mass., 1993), p. 68. For Kuhn’s philosophy of science, a historical approach is essential. On this point, I basically agree with Wes Sharrock and Rupert Read, Kuhn: Philosopher of Scientific Revolution (Cambridge, 2002). Compare with Toulmin’s call to “return to reason” in his Return to Reason (n. 40). Toulmin’s “reason” seems to me to be, especially, historical reason. But, such a call was already in George Sarton, The History of Science and the New Humanism (New York, 1956: First Published in 1931). Sarton states in “The Teaching of the History of Science (Second Article),” Isis, 4 (1921–22), p. 249: “The historian of science will constitute the vanguard of the New Humanism.”

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sasaki, C. (2003). Conclusion. In: Descartes’s Mathematical Thought. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 237. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1225-5_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1225-5_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6487-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1225-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics