Skip to main content

Rethinking Rationality: From Bleak Implications to Darwinian Modules

  • Chapter
Cognition, Agency and Rationality

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 79))

Abstract

There is a venerable philosophical tradition that views human beings as intrinsically rational, though even the most ardent defender of this view would admit that under certain circumstances people’s decisions and thought processes can be very irrational indeed. When people are extremely tired, or drunk, or in the grip of rage, they sometimes reason and act in ways that no account of rationality would condone. About thirty years ago, Amos Tversky, Daniel Kahneman and a number of other psychologists began reporting findings suggesting much deeper problems with the traditional idea that human beings are intrinsically rational animals. What these studies demonstrated is that even under quite ordinary circumstances where fatigue, drugs and strong emotions are not factors, people reason and make judgments in ways that systematically violate familiar canons of rationality on a wide array of problems. Those first surprising studies sparked the growth of a major research tradition whose impact has been felt in economics, political theory, medicine and other areas far removed from cognitive science. In Section 2, we will sketch a few of the better known experimental findings in this area. We’ve chosen these particular findings because they will play a role at a later stage of the paper. For readers who would like a deeper and more systematic account of the fascinating and disquieting research on reasoning and judgment, there are now several excellent texts and anthologies available. (Nisbett and Ross 1980, Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky 1982, Baron 1988, Piatelli-Palmarini 1994, Dawes 1988, Sutherland 1994).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Barkow, J. 1992: Beneath new culture is old psychology: Gossip and social stratification. In Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby 1992, 627–637.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkow, J., Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (eds.), 1992: The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, J. 1988: Thinking and Deciding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baron-Cohen, S. 1994: How to build a baby that can read minds: Cognitive mechanisms in mindreading. Cahiers de Psychologie, 13, 5, 513–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1995: Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. and Spelke, E. 1994: Domain-specific knowledge and conceptual change. In Hirschfeld and Gelman 1994, 169–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. (eds.), 1996: Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casscells, W., Schoenberger, A. and Grayboys, T. 1978: Interpretation by physicians of clinical laboratory results. New England Journal of Medicine, 299, 999–1000.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, L. and Chapman, J. 1967: Genesis of popular but erroneous diagnostic observations. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 72, 193–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, L. and Chapman, J. 1969: Illusory correlation as an obstacle to the use of valid psychodiagnostic signs. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 74, 271–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, P. and Holyoak, K. 1985: Pragmatic reasoning schemas. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 391–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, P. and Holyoak, K. 1989: On the natural selection of reasoning theories. Cognition, 33, 285–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, P., Holyoak, K., Nisbett, R., and Oliver, L. 1986: Pragmatic versus syntactic approaches to training deductive reasoning. Cognitive Psychology, 18, 293–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1965: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chomsky, N. 1975: Reflections of Language. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1980: Rules and Representations. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. 1981: Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 4, 317–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, L. 1986: The Dialogue of Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L. 1989: The logic of social exchange: Has natural selection shaped how humans reason? Studies with Wason Selection Task. Cognition, 31, 187–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1992: Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby 1992, 163–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1994: Origins of domain specificity: The evolution of functional organization. In Hirschfeld and Gelman 1994, 85–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. 1996: Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgment under uncertainty.“ Cognition, 58, 1, 1–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, D. 1996: Evidence for the innateness of deontic reasoning. Mind and Language, 11, 160–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawes, R. 1988: Rational Choice in an Uncertain World. Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes, R. 1994: House of Cards: Psychology and Psychotherapy Built on Myth. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiedler, K. 1988: The dependence ofthe conjunction fallacy on subtle linguistic factors. Psychological Research, 50, 123–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1983: The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1986: The modularity of mind. In Pylyshyn and Demopoulos 1986, 3–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. 1990: The Organization of Learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, H. 1983: Frames of Mind: The Theory of Multiple Intelligences. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J. (ed.), 1987: Modularity in Knowledge Representation and Natural-Language Understanding. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S. and Brenneman K. 1994: First principles can support both universal and culture-specific learning about number and music. In Hirschfeld and Gelman 1994, 369–387 )

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. 1991: How to make cognitive illusions disappear: Beyond `heuristics and biases.’European Review of Social Psychology, 2, 83–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. 1994: Why the distinction between single-event probabilities and frequencies is important for psychology (and vice versa): In G. Wright and P. Ayton, eds., Subjective Probability. New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. and Hug, K. 1992: Domain-specific reasoning: Social contracts, cheating and perspective change. Cognition, 43, 127–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., and Hoffrage, U. 1995: How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instruction: Frequency formats. Psychological Review, 102, 684–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., Hoffrage, U., and Kleinbölting, H. 1991: Probabilistic mental models: A Brunswikean theory of confidence. Psychological Review, 98, 506–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. and Murray, D. 1987: Cognition as Intuitive Statistics, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T., Vallone, B. and Tversky, A. 1985: The hot.hand in basketball: On the misconception of random sequences. Cognitive Psychology, 17, 295–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gluck, M. and Bower, G. 1988: From conditioning to category learning: An adaptive network model. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 117, 227–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 1994: A modern history theory of functions. Nous, 28, 344–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. 1986: Epistemology and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. 1992: Bully for Brontosaurus. Further Reflections in Natural History. London: Pengu in Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griggs, R. and Cox, J. 1982: The elusive thematic-materials effect in Wason’s selection task. British Journal of Psychology, 73, 407–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. 1997: What Emotions Really Are. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. 1985: Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hertwig, R. and Gigerenzer, G. 1994: The chain of reasoning in the conjunction task. Unpublished manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschfeld, L. and Gelman, S. (eds.), 1994: Mapping the Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. 1980: Culture and Inference: A Trobriand Case Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. 1992: Is there a faculty of social cognition? In R. Jackendoff, Languages of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 69–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. 1973: On the psychology of prediction. Psychological Review, 80, 237–251. Reprinted in Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky 1982

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. 1996: On the reality of cognitive illusions. Psychological Review, 103, 582–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P. and Tversky, A. 1982: Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff-Smith, A. 1992: Beyond Modularity: A Developmental Perspective on Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehman, D, Lempert, R and Nisbett, R. 1988: The effects of graduate education on reasoning: Formal discipline and thinking about everyday life events. American Psychologist, 43, 431–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehman, D. and Nisbett, R. 1990: A longitudinal study of the effects of undergraduate education on reasoning. Developmental Psychology, 26, 952–960.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. 1994: ToMM, ToBY, and agency: Core architecture and domain specificity. In Hirschfeld and Gelman 1994, 119–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichtenstein, S., Fischoff, B. and Phillips, L. 1982: “Calibration of probabilities: The state of the art to 1980. In Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky 1982, 306–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manktelow, K. and Over, D. 1995: Deontic reasoning. In S. Newstead and J. St. B. Evans, eds, Perspectives on Thinking and reasoning. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. 1991: The teleological notion of `function’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 59, 454–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. and Ross, L. 1980: Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R., Fong, G, Lehman, D. and Cheng, P. 1987: Teaching reasoning. Science, 238, 625–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M. and Chater, N. 1994: A rational analysis of the selection task as optimal data selection.Psychological Review, 101, 608–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piattelli-Palmarini, M. 1994: Inevitable Illusions: How Mistakes of Reason Rule Our Minds. New York: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. 1994: The Language Instinct. New York: William Morrow and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. 1997: How the Mind Works. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. 1993: Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. 1984: Computation and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. and Demopoulos, W. (eds.), 1986: Meaning and Cognitive Structure: Issues in the Computational Theory of Mind. New Jersey: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quartz, S. and Sejnowski, T. 1994: Beyond modularity: Neural constructivist principles in evelopment. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17, 725–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (in preparation a): Evolutionary psychology and the massive modularity hypothesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (in preparation b): How to dissolve the rationality debate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal, G. 1996: The modularity of theory of mind. In Carruthers and Smith 1995, 141157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P., Fischhoff, B., and Lichtenstein, S. 1976: Cognitive processes and societal risk taking. In J. S. Carol and J. W. Payne, eds, Cognition and Social Behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D. 1994: The modularity of thought and the epidemiology of representations. In Hirschfeld and Gelman 1994, 39–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., Cara, F. and Girotto, V. 1995: Relevance theory explains the selection task. Cognition, 57, 1, 1995.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. 1996: Without Good Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. 1990: The Fragmentation of Reason. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutherland, S. 1994: Irrationality: Why We Don’t Think Straight New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanenhaus, M., Dell, G., and Carlson, G. 1987: Context effects and lexical processing: A connectionist approach to modularity. In Garfield 1987, 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. 1992: The psychological foundations of culture. In Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby 1992, 19–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J. and Cosmides, L. 1995: Foreword. In Baron-Cohen 1995, xi-xviii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. 1971: The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46, 35–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1983: Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The conjunction fallacy in probability judgement. Psychological Review, 90, 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. 1982: Judgments of and by representativeness. In Kahneman, Slovic and Tversky 1982, 84–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. and Daly, M. 1992: The man who mistook his wife for a chattel. In Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby 1992, 289–322.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Samuels, R., Stich, S., Tremoulet, P.D. (1999). Rethinking Rationality: From Bleak Implications to Darwinian Modules. In: Korta, K., Sosa, E., Arrazola, X. (eds) Cognition, Agency and Rationality. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 79. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1070-1_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-1070-1_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5321-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-1070-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics