Skip to main content

Religious Experience and Religious Epistemology

  • Chapter
Analytic Philosophy of Religion

Part of the book series: Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion ((HCPR,volume 3))

  • 434 Accesses

Abstract

The twentieth century saw significant new developments in and significant new directions for the treatments of religious experience and religious epistemology. The philosophical discussions in these areas have now taken on significant new dimensions. While natural theology, based upon evidentialism, dominated Anglo-American analytic philosophy in the early part of the twentieth century, antievidentialism — either in the various forms of religious experience, Reformed epistemology, or fideism — became very dominant in the last few decades of the century.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See, for example, Roderick Chisholm, Perceiving: A Philosophical Study (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Edmund Gettier, “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis, Vol. 23, 1963. Reprinted in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Louis P. Pojman (New York: Wadsworth, 1999), pp. 142–43.

    Google Scholar 

  3. William K. Clifford, “The Ethics of Belief,” from Lectures and Essays, 1879. Reprinted in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Louis P. Pojman, p. 551.

    Google Scholar 

  4. William K. Clifford, “The Ethics of Belief,” from Lectures and Essays, 1879. Reprinted in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Louis P. Pojman, p. 554.

    Google Scholar 

  5. William K. Clifford, “The Ethics of Belief,” from Lectures and Essays, 1879. Reprinted in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings, edited by Louis P. Pojman

    Google Scholar 

  6. William James, Pragmatism (New York: New American Library, 1907), pp. 22ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. William James, “The Will to Believe,” in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings,edited by Louis Pojman, p. 558.

    Google Scholar 

  8. William James, “The Will to Believe,” in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings,edited by Louis Pojman, p. 555.

    Google Scholar 

  9. William James, “The Will to Believe,” in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings,edited by Louis Pojman, p. 558.

    Google Scholar 

  10. William James, “The Will to Believe,” in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings,edited by Louis Pojman, p. 559.

    Google Scholar 

  11. William James, “The Will to Believe,” in The Theory of Knowledge: Classical and Contemporary Readings,edited by Louis Pojman, p. 559.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., p. 556. There are many discussions that compare Pascal and James. For example, see J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), pp. 200–203.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Pascal may respond that if a person behaves religiously (for example, by praying or using holy water), then religious belief will gradually and eventually follow, but such a response seems very optimistic and belies what is known of human psychology. James maintains that there are, of course, other difficulties with Pascal’s wager. For example, obviously God may punish a person for believing on such grounds. See James, ibid., 556.

    Google Scholar 

  14. However, Nicholas Wolterstorff disagrees that evidentialism is tied so closely to natural theology. See his “The Migration of the Theistic Arguments: From Natural Theology to Evidential Apologetics,” in Rationality, Religious Belief and Moral Commitment, edited by Robert Audi and William J. Wainwright (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1986), pp. 38ff. Wolterstorff attributes evidentialism to the philosophical influence of the Enlightenment.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Antony Flew,“The Presumption of Atheism,” in The Presumption of Atheism and Other Philosophical Essays on God, Freedom,and Immortality, Antony Flew (New York: Barnes and Noble Books, 1976), pp. 22–23.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Thus, the cumulative case argument is not simply an accumulation of different arguments. For a helpful discussion that illustrates the point nicely, see Caroline Franks Davis, The Evidential Force of Religious Experience (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), pp. 108ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Basil Mitchell, The Justification of Religious Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981), and Richard Swinbume, The Existence of God (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  18. The following are some of the primary contemporary sources that treat the distinction between religious and mystical experiences and also address the comparison of religious experience with sense experience: George Mavrodes, Belief in God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience (New York: Random House, 1970); C. B. Martin, Religious Belief (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1959); Michael Martin, Atheism: A Philosophical Study (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1990); Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1958); Wayne Proudfoot, Religious Experience (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985); William Rowe, “Religious Experience and the Principle of Credulity,” International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 13, 1982, pp. 8592; Ninian Smart, The Religious Experience (London: Macmillan, 1991); T. Stace, Mysticism and Philosophy (New York: Macmillan, 1960); William Wainwright, Mysticism (Madison, Wis.: University of Wisconsin Press, 1981); William Wainwright, “Mysticism and Sense Perception,” Religious Studies, Vol. 9, 1973. Much of this article appears as Chapter 3 of his Mysticism and is reprinted in Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, edited by Steven Cahn and David Shatz (Oxford: University of Oxford Press, 1982), pp. 123–45; Keith Yandell, The Epistemology of Religious Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993). Also see the discussion of William Alston’s Perceiving God below and references cited there. The source that provided the framework for much of the discussion in the twentieth century was William James, The Varieties of Religious Experience (New York: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1902).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 246. This definition is followed closely by William Alston, discussed below, in his theory of the perception of God.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God, p. 245–46. Alston uses the same theory of appearing and follows a very similar tactic in his perception of God, discussed below. Interestingly, William Rowe, who opposes claims concerning the cognitive content of religious experience, first suggests this position in “Religious Experience and the Principle of Credulity,” International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 13, 1982, pp. 85–92.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ib id., pp. 249. Also, see Otto, ibid., and William Wainwright, Mysticism (Madison, Wis.: University of Wisconsin Press, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  23. C. D. Broad, “Arguments for the Existence of God, II,” The Journal of Theological Studies, Vol. 40, 1939.

    Google Scholar 

  24. William Wainwright has drawn the comparison between religious experience and sense experience earlier in a similar fashion. See William Wainwright, Mysticism, Chapter 3. Much of this chapter is drawn from his “Mysticism and Sense Perception,” Religious Studies, Vol. 9, 1973, pp. 25778. The article is reprinted in Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, edited by Steven Cahn and David Shatz.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God, pp. 255–56.

    Google Scholar 

  26. One person who raises such an objection is Roderick Chisholm. See ibid., pp. 257–58.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., pp. 271–72. Swinburne thinks that there are normally no special circumstances that would legitimately make one doubt the veracity of a person’s report of religious experiences.

    Google Scholar 

  28. It is the application of POC to religious experience rather than POC itself as a general epistemological principle that is most at issue. Rowe emphasizes this point in “Religious Experience and the Principle of Credulity,” ibid.,pp. 90–91.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God, p. 256.

    Google Scholar 

  30. J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., p. 183. It may very well be that even granting that such experience can determine that the power (being?) is friendly rather than unfriendly (God rather than Satan) is granting too much. See the discussion of William Alston’s appeal to direct reference later in this chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Paul Henle, “Uses of the Ontological Argument,” Philosophical Review, Vol. 70, 1961, pp. 102ff.

    Google Scholar 

  33. William Wainwright, Mysticism,pp. 88ff.

    Google Scholar 

  34. William Rowe, “Religious Experience and the Principle of Credulity,” pp. 90ff. Also see David Conway, “Mavrodes, Martin, and the Verification of Religious Experience,” International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 2, no. 3, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  35. The problem of determining correctly the reference of “God” during a religious experience is treated in detail below in the discussion of William Alston’s Perceiving God.

    Google Scholar 

  36. For a response to Rowe, see Keith Yandell, The Epistemology of Religious Experience, pp. 229–30.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Wayne Proudfoot, Religious Experience (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985), pp. 196ff.

    Google Scholar 

  38. This analysis is based upon an example used by Proudfoot, ibid., pp. 192–93.

    Google Scholar 

  39. William Wainwright, ibid., p. 86–87. It is worth noting that these criteria appear to be codified in William Alston’s notion of a Christian mystical doxastic practice (CMP), discussed below.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See Caroline Franks Davis, The Evidential Force of Religious Experience (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), Chapter 5.

    Google Scholar 

  41. John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion: Human Responses to the Transcendent (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1989). See the excerpt reprinted in Contemporary Perspectives on Religious Epistemology, edited by R. Douglas Geivett and Brendan Sweetman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), p. 316.

    Google Scholar 

  42. John Hick, An Interpretation of Religion: Human Responses to the Transcendent (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1989). See the excerpt reprinted in Contemporary Perspectives on Religious Epistemology, edited by R. Douglas Geivett and Brendan Sweetman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 316–17.

    Google Scholar 

  43. John Hick, “Religious Faith as Experiencing-As,” in Classical and Contemporary Readings in the Philosophy of Religion, edited by John Hick (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1964, 1990), p. 409.

    Google Scholar 

  44. See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe (New York: Macmillan, 1953), Part II, Section xi.

    Google Scholar 

  45. John Hick, “Religious Faith as Experiencing-As,” p. 409.

    Google Scholar 

  46. William P. Alston, Perceiving God (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991), p. 100. For a précis of this book, see William P. Alston, “Précis of Perceiving God,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 54, no. 4, 1994.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Several critical issues are raised by the respondents in the Alston Symposium in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,Vol. 54, no. 4, 1994, including Richard Gale, “Why Alston’s Mystical Doxastic Practice Is Subjective,” George Pappas, “Perception and Mystical Experience,” and Robert Adams, “Religious Disagreements and Doxastic Practices.” See also William Hasker, “On Justifying the Christian Practice,” The New Scholasticism, Vol. 60, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  48. For a more constructive suggestion and optimistic outlook for Alston’s defense of CMP, see the following two articles by Philip L. Quinn: “And Thinner Theologies: Hick and Alston on Religious Diversity,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 38, 1995, pp. 145–64. Reprinted in The Philosophical Challenge of Religious Diversity, edited by Philip L. Quinn and Kevin Meeker (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), especially pp. 235ff; and “Religious Diversity and Religious Toleration,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 49, 2001, pp. 1–24. Quinn’s treatment of Alston is discussed in Chapter IX.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Robert Adams suggests that more emphasis should be placed on the individual’s belief rather than the social nature of the doxastic practice, but he does not develop this point. See Robert Adams, “Religious Disagreements and Doxastic Practices,” p. 886.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Arguably, equally for Roman Catholics and non-Catholic Christians alike since the legend of St. Joan is now so thoroughly embedded in Western folklore. Other saints have reported not being so sure of the source of their religious experiences at the time that they were having them. See St. Teresa, Interior Castle (London: Thomas Baker Publishing, 1930).

    Google Scholar 

  51. For Alston’s comparison of SP and CMP on this score, see Perceiving God,Chapter 3 and pp. 250ff.

    Google Scholar 

  52. For further criticism of Alston on the grounds that nonsensory perception of God is subjective, see Richard Gale, “Why Alston’s Mystical Doxastic Practice Is Subjective,” pp. 869–75.

    Google Scholar 

  53. William Alston, Perceiving God,pp. 96–97.

    Google Scholar 

  54. While Alston distinguishes between S’s being justified and S’s knowing that he is justified in believing that he is being appeared to by God, still unless there is some indication of what might be the criterion for determining whether S is right or wrong in believing that the properties that x presents in appearing to S are sufficient for identifying God, then there is no reason to maintain that it is reasonable to believe that S is being appeared to by God.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Richard Gale, “Why Alston’s Mystical Doxastic Practice Is Subjective,” pp. 871ff.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Richard B. Miller, “The Reference of `God,”` Faith and Philosophy, Vol. 3, no. 1, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  57. William P. Alston, “Referring to God,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion,Vol. 24, no. 3, November 1988, pp. 10–12. Reprinted in Divine Nature and Human Language: Essays in Philosophical Theology, William P. Alston (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  58. See Keith Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions,” in Readings in the Philosophy of Language,edited by Jay Rosenberg and Charles Travis (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall), p. 198, and James F. Harris, “The Causal Theory of Reference and Religious Language,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 29, 1991, pp. 82–83.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Harris, See Keith Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions,” in Readings in the Philosophy of Language,edited by Jay Rosenberg and Charles Travis (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall), p. 198, and James F. Harris, “The Causal Theory of Reference and Religious Language,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 29, 1991, p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  60. See Keith Donnellan, “Reference and Definite Descriptions,” in Readings in the Philosophy of Language,edited by Jay Rosenberg and Charles Travis (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall), p. 198, and James F. Harris, “The Causal Theory of Reference and Religious Language,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 29, 1991, pp. 83–84.

    Google Scholar 

  61. See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Section 79.

    Google Scholar 

  62. James Harris, “The Causal Theory of Reference and Religious Language,” pp. 84–85. 89 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Section 79.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Plantinga has developed his position in a number of different writings, including the following: “Is Belief in God Rational?” in Rationality and Religious Belief, edited by C. F. Delaney (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1979); “Is Belief in God Properly Basic,” Nous,Vol. 15, 1981, pp. 41–51; “Rationality and Religious Belief,” in Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, edited by Steven Cahn and David Shatz (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982). Parts of this article come from two previous articles: “Reason and Belief in God,” in Faith and Rationality, edited by Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983); and “Epistemic Justification,” Nous,Vol. 20, 1986, pp. 3–18. See especially “Rationality and Religious Belief,” pp. 25562.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Alvin Plantinga, “Rationality and Religious Belief,” p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Nicholas Wolterstorff, “Introduction,” in Faith and Rationality, edited by Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Alvin Plantings, “Rationality and Religious Belief,” pp. 48ff.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Alvin Plantinga, “The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology,” Christian Scholar’s Review, Vol. 11, no. 3, 1982. Page numbers refer to reprint in Philosophy of Religion: Selected Readings, edited by Michael Peterson, William Hasker, Bruce Reichenbach, and David Basinger (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996); Nicholas Wolterstorff, “The Migration of the Theistic Arguments: From Natural Theology to Evidentialist Apologetics,” in Rationality, Religious Belief,and Moral Commitment, edited by Robert Audi and William J. Wainwright (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1986); and “The Reformed Tradition,” in A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion, edited by Philip L. Quinn and Charles Taliaferro (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1997), pp. 165–70.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Alvin Plantinga, “Rationality and Religious Belief,” pp. 76–77.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Terence Penelhum, God and Skepticism (Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel, 1983), p. 30 and pp. 146–47. Penelhum groups Plantinga with Pascal and Kierkegaard as an evangelical fideist — a label that Plantinga disavows (see his “Reason and Belief in God,” p. 90). The question of fideism aside, Penelhum’s parity argument does capture Plantinga’s general epistemological strategy of treating belief in God in the same manner as secular, common-sense beliefs, so I will use this designation for Plantinga’s approach. I discuss the issue of fideism below.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Alvin Plantinga, “Rationality and Religious Belief,” p. 271.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Some take the import of Reformed epistemology to be positive while others take it to be purely negative, that is, some take Reformed epistemology to build a positive case for the Reformed platform while others take it to simply shift the burden of proof to those who would oppose the Reformed platform. See especially Richard Grigg, “Theism and Proper Basicality: A Response to Plantinga,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 14, 1983, pp. 123–27. My own reading of Plantinga is that he attempts to build a positive case for the Reformed platform, but this reading is not uncontroversial. See, for example, Mark McLeod, “The Analogy Argument for the Proper Basicality of Belief in God,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 21, 1987, pp. 3–20.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Alvin Plantinga, “Rationality and Religious Belief,” ibid., p. 273.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Terence Penelhum, Reason and Religious Faith (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1995), p. 95. The fact that Plantinga himself anticipates this objection and tries to respond to it has not prevented his critics from pressing the issue, and several have, including David Basinger, “Reformed Epistemology and Hick’s Religious Pluralism,” in Philosophy of Religion, edited by Michael Peterson et al. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), pp. 336–46; Jay M. Van Hook, “Knowledge, Belief, and Reformed Epistemology,” The Reformed Journal, Vol. 32, 1981, p. 16; and William Alston, “Plantinga’s Epistemology of Religious Belief,” in Alvin Plantinga, edited by J. E. Tomberlin and Peter van Inwagen (Dordrecht, Among: D. Reidel, 1985), pp. 300–301. For the effects of Plantinga’s position on relativism and religious pluralism, see William Lad Sessions, “Plantinga’s Box,” Faith and Philosophy, Vol. 8, no. 1, 1991, pp. 51–66.

    Google Scholar 

  74. An example taken from the cartoon strip `Peanuts“ and, ironically, an example I’ve used in class for over twenty years to illustrate Hume’s point of how the evidence for the argument from design underdetermines the appropriate analogy to be used.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Alvin Plantinga, “The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology,” p. 318.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See Gary Gutting, Religious Belief and Skepticism (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See Gary Gutting, Religious Belief and Skepticism (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982)

    Google Scholar 

  78. Nicholas Wolterstorff, Reason within the Bounds of Religion (Grand Rapids, Mich.: William B. Eerdmans, 1976), p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ibid., p. 66. It should be noted that Wolterstorff intends that control beliefs should function generally this way for the Christian scholar in his weighing of such scientific theories as Copernican astronomy and Darwinian evolutionary theory. See ibid., p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Terence Penelhum, God and Skepticism, pp. 146ff.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Alvin Plantinga, “Reason and Belief in God,” p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  82. For further comparison of Penelhum and Plantinga on this point and discussion of different forms of the parity argument, see Richard Askew, “On Fideism and Alvin Plantinga,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 23, 1988, pp. 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Stephen Wykstra, “Review of Faith and Rationality,” Faith and Philosophy, Vol. 3, 1986, p. 209.

    Google Scholar 

  84. For further discussion of this point, see Robert Pargetter, “Experience, Proper Basicality, and Belief in God,” in Contemporary Perspectives on Religious Epistemology,edited by R. Douglas Geivett and Brendan Sweetman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 150–67.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Alvin Plantinga, Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). The earlier volumes were Warrant and Proper Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993) and Warrant: The Current Debate (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  86. There are different interpretations of Kierkegaard on this point. See, for example, C. Stephen Evans, “Kierkegaard and Plantinga on Belief in God: Subjectivity as the Ground of Properly Basic Religious Beliefs,” Faith and Philosophy,Vol. 5, no. 1, 1988, pp. 25–39, and “The Epistemological Significance of Transformative Religious Experiences: A Kierkegaardian Exploration,” Faith and Philosophy,Vol. 8, no. 2, 1991, pp. 180–92; and Marilyn Gaye Piety, “Kierkegaard on Rationality,” Faith and Philosophy, Vol. 10, no. 3, 1993, pp. 365–79.

    Google Scholar 

  87. For a discussion of different forms of fideism, see Terence Penelhum, “Fideism,” in A Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Philip L. Quinn and Charles Taliaferro (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1997), pp. 376–82.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Norman Malcolm develops this point regarding the limit of explanation more fully in Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View? (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1994), Chapter 6. Also see Peter Winch’s comments in the same volume in his discussion of Malcolm’s essay, pp. 103ff. Winch makes the important point that it was the particular kind of explanation that depends upon a theory of meaning that Wittgenstein opposed (according to which the meaning of a word is given in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, that is, essentialism). The important thing is not simply that explanation comes to an end but that confusions about the nature of language and meaning make philosophers ignore or resist this fact.

    Google Scholar 

  89. For a more complete listing of additional tenets of Wittgensteinian fideism, see Kai Nielsen, “Wittgensteinian Fideism,” Philosophy,Vol. 42, no. 161, 1967, pp. 192–93.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Peter Winch, The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,1958), and “Understanding a Primitive Society,” American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 1, 1964, pp. 307–25. Page numbers refer to the reprint in Rationality,edited by Bryan R. Wilson (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1970). Norman Malcolm, “Anselm’s Ontological Arguments,” Philosophical Review, Vol. 69, no. 1, January 1960 (page numbers refer to the reprint in Malcolm’s Knowledge and Certainty [Englewood, Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963]), and “The Groundlessness of Belief,” in Reason and Religion, edited by Stuart Brown (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1977), which is reprinted in Contemporary Perspectives on Religious Epistemology,edited by R. Douglas Geivett and Brendan Sweetman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 92–103, to which the page numbers here refer.

    Google Scholar 

  91. See Malcolm, “The Groundlessness of Belief,” pp. 92–94.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty (New York: Harper and Row, 1969), § 192.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Malcolm, “The Groundlessness of Belief,” p. 96–98.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Section 292, and Malcolm, ibid., p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Malcolm, “The Groundlessness of Belief,” p. 98. Also see Norman Malcolm, Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1994), Chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  96. See Patrick Sherry, “Is Religion a `Form of Life’?” American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 9, no. 2, 1972, especially pp. 164ff. Sherry distinguishes what he calls the relativist/conventionalist and the pragmatic/empiricist interpretations of Wittgenstein. Winch and Phillips fall into the more radical relativist/conventionalist group. Further criticism of the relativist/conventionalist interpretation of Wittgenstein and defense of universal epistemological notions such as truth and reason are found in Patrick Sherry, Religion,Truth and Language Games (London: Macmillan, 1977), and William P. Alston, “The Christian Language-Game,” in The Autonomy of Religious Belief (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), pp. 128–62. As I discuss below, the degree of autonomy enjoyed by language-games and the nature of the relationships among different language-games are complex and difficult issues. For further discussion of Malcolm’s claims of the groundlessness of religious belief, see the exchange from the 1975 symposium among Malcolm, Colin Lyas, and Basil Mitchell in Reason and Religion, edited by Stuart C. Brown (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  97. Peter Winch, The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy. The same ideas are further developed in his “Understanding a Primitive Society,” pp. 78–111.

    Google Scholar 

  98. E. E. Evans-Pritchard, Witchcraft,Oracles and Magic among the Azande (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1937).

    Google Scholar 

  99. Peter Winch, “Understanding a Primitive Society,” pp. 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  100. I have argued this point more fully in James F. Harris, Against Relativism (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1992), pp. 100ff.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Phillips distinguishes his view from that of Braithwaite and calls Braithwaite’ s views “confused.” See his Religion without Explanation (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1976), pp. 140ff.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Michael J. Coughlan, “Wittgenstein, Language, and Religious Belief,” in God in Language, edited by Robert P. Scharlemann and Gilbert E. M. Ogutu (New York: Paragon House Publishers, 1987), p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  103. For example, see D. Z. Phillips, The Concept of Prayer (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1965); Religion without Explanation (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1976); and Faith and Philosophical Inquiry (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1970). Also see “Religious Beliefs and Language-Games,” in The Philosophy of Wittgenstein.: Aesthetics, Ethics, and Religion, edited by John Canfield (New York: Garland, 1986), and in Faith and Philosophical Inquiry as Chapter V.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Throughout this discussion of language-game fideism, I use the expressions “the religious language-game” and “the theistic language-game.” Determining the boundaries and varieties of language-games is not an issue I can address here. W. D. Hudson uses the expression “the theistic language-game” and calls Christianity a language-game in Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Bearing of His Philosophy upon Religious Belief (Richmond, Va.: John Knox Press, 1968), pp. 69 and 70. As I have noted above, Malcolm describes religion and science as two different language-games in “The Groundlessness of Belief,” ibid., p. 100, and specifically includes nontheistic Buddhism as part of the religious language-game, ibid., p. 101. Phillips speaks of “religious language-games” (in the plural). For further discussion of this point, see R. H. Bell, “Wittgenstein and Descriptive Theology,” Religious Studies, Oct. 1969, and Patrick Sherry, “Is Religion a Form of Life,” American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 9, no. 2, 1972. There is obviously not a single language-game of religion or a single language-game of theism and, hence, no single grammar of religious language. It may be helpful to think of a religion or theism as aggregates of different language-games. Religion and science would then differ not by each being a different discrete language-game but by each being different aggregates of different language-games, some of which may be common to the two different aggregates

    Google Scholar 

  105. However, as Phillips has indicated in correspondence, “no additional `entity”` does not necessarily mean “no addition at all.” Certainly, when the theist affirms God’s existence, he is affirming something “additional” about the world. Compare what Wittgenstein said about pain: it is not a “something,” but it is not a “nothing” either.

    Google Scholar 

  106. See Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics,Psychology and Religious Belief,edited by Cyril Barrett (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1966), pp. 53–72.

    Google Scholar 

  107. D. Z. Phillips, “Religious Beliefs and Language-Games,” p. 223.

    Google Scholar 

  108. See Phillips, ibid.,and The Concept of Prayer,Chapter I.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Michael Coughlan, “Wittgenstein, Language, and Religious Beliefs,” p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  110. See D. Z. Phillips, “Religious Beliefs and Language-Games,” p. 111.

    Google Scholar 

  111. See, for example, R. W. Hepburn, “From World to God,” Mind, Vol. 72, 1963; Kai Nielson, “Wittgensteinian Fideism,” Philosophy,July 1967, reprinted in John Canfield, The Philosophy of Wittgenstein (New York: Garland, 1986), and Kai Nielsen, “A Critique of Wittgensteinian Fideism,” in The Autonomy of Religious Belie: A Critical Inquiry, edited by Frederick Crosson (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981). This last piece also appears in Philosophy of Religion: Selected Readings,Third Edition, edited by William L. Rowe and William J. Wainwright (Fort Worth, Tex.: Harcourt Brace College Publishers, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  112. In correspondence with the author. What this position ignores is that claims about the grammar of a language-game must rely upon someone’s intuitions.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Peter Winch, Trying to Make Sense (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987), pp. 134ff.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Peter Winch, Trying to Make Sense (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987), pp. 135–36.

    Google Scholar 

  115. William P. Alston, “Taking the Curse Off Language-Games: A Realist Account of Doxastic Practices,” in Philosophy and the Grammar of Religious Belief, edited by Timothy Tessin and Mario von der Ruhr (London: St. Martin’s Press, 1995), pp. 24–25.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Ibid., pp. 30ff. For discussion of the differences between Phillips and Alston, see M. Jamie Ferreira, “Universal Criteria and the Autonomy of Religious Belief,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 15, 1984, pp. 3–12.

    Google Scholar 

  117. D. Z. Phillips, Religion without Explanation, p.174. Phillips explicitly anticipates the charge of defending a “disguised atheism” on pp. 149ff.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief, p. 59. Quoted by Phillips in Religion without Explanation, pp. 174–75.

    Google Scholar 

  119. For a full discussion of such criticisms and Phillips’s reply, see his Belief Change and Forms of Life (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press International, 1986), Chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ibid., p. 33. See pp. 26–33 for Phillips’s complete reply. Also see D. Z. Phillips, “Belief, Change and Forms of Life: The Confusions of Externalism and Intemalism” in The Autonomy of Religious Belief, edited by Frederick J. Crossen (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), for detailed textual references for his views regarding the possibility of criticizing religious beliefs, especially pp. 85–90.

    Google Scholar 

  121. This line of criticism has been urged by others: See W. D. Hudson, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Bearing of His Philosophy upon Religious Belief, pp. 68ff; Patrick Sherry, “Is Religion a `Form of Life’?” pp. 165; and Kai Nielsen, “Wittgensteinian Fidesim,” p. 209.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Further discussions of Wittgensteinian language-games and religious beliefs are found in Richard Bell, “Theology as Grammar: Is God an Object of Understanding,” Religious Studies, Vol. 11, 1975, pp. 307–17; Alan Brunton, “A Model for the Religious Philosophy of D. Z. Phillips,” Analysis, Vol. 31, 1970–71, pp. 43–48; Dallas M. High, “Belief, Falsification, and Wittgenstein,” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 3, 1972, pp. 240–50; James Kellenberger, “The Language-Game View of Religion and Religious Certainty,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 2, no. 2, 1972, pp. 255–75; and Fergus Kerr, Theology after Wittgenstein (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Harris, J.F. (2002). Religious Experience and Religious Epistemology. In: Analytic Philosophy of Religion. Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0719-0_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0719-0_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5983-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0719-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics