Advertisement

Actions and Inconsistency: The Closure Problem of Practical Reasoning

  • Douglas Walton
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 266)

Abstract

This article formulates a fundamental problem in the philosophy of action. It will become apparent that the same problem is also an abstract and general, but very important question for the field of artificial intelligence — and robotics in particular. As well, the nature of the problem, as revealed below, will make evident its importance in the field of logical evaluation of natural language argumentation. The problem is one of when a knowledge-based goal-directed inference leading to an action (or a recommendation for a course of action to be taken) may be said to be structurally correct (or closed), parallel to the sense in which a deductive argument is said to be valid (deductively closed).

Keywords

Practical Reasoning Argumentation Scheme Closure Problem Logical Inconsistency Deductive Argument 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Aquinas, Thomas (1970), Summa Theologiae, vol. 17. Trans. Thomas Gilby, Blackfriars Edition, New York, McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  2. Aristotle (1954), The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. Trans, and ed. by Sir David Ross, London, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Audi, Robert (1989), Practical Reasoning. London, Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. Clarke, D.S., Jr. (1985), Practical Inferences. London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  5. Clarke, D.S., Jr. (1989), Rational Acceptance and Purpose: An Outline of a Pragmatist Epistemology. Totowa, New Jersey, Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  6. Cuomo, Mario M. (1984), “Religious Belief and Public Morality,” New York Review of Books 31, 32–37.Google Scholar
  7. Hamblin, C.L. (1970), Fallacies. London, Methuen.Google Scholar
  8. Hamblin, C.L. (1987), Imperatives. Oxford, Blackwell.Google Scholar
  9. Honderich, Ted (1995), The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Jonsen, Albert R. and Stephen Toulmin (1988), The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning. Berkeley, University of California Press.Google Scholar
  11. Krabbe, E.C.W. (1990), “Inconsistent Commitments and Commitment to Inconsistencies,” Informal Logic 12, 33–42.Google Scholar
  12. Reiter, Raymond (1980), “A Logic for Default Reasoning,” Artificial Intelligence 13, 81–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Reiter, Raymond (1987), “Nonmonotonic Reasoning,” Annual Review of Computer Science 2, 147–186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Russell, Stuart and Peter Norvig (1995), Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach. Upper Saddle River, New Jersey, Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  15. Simon, H. (1978), “Rationality as a Process and as a Product of Thought,” American Economic Review 68, 1–16.Google Scholar
  16. Singh, Munidar Paul (1994), Multiagent Systems. Berlin, Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
  17. Tuomela, Raimo (1992), “Group Beliefs,” Synthese 91, 285–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Walton, Douglas N. (1989), Informal Logic. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Walton, Douglas N. (1990), Practical Reasoning: Goal-Driven, Knowledge-Based, Action-Guiding Argumentation. Savage, Maryland, Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  20. Walton, Douglas N. and Erik C.W. Krabbe (1995), Commitment in Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning. Albany, State University of New York Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 1997

Authors and Affiliations

  • Douglas Walton
    • 1
  1. 1.University of WinnipegCanada

Personalised recommendations