Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 66))

Abstract

In order to determine whether two participants in a discussion are in real dis/ agreement one must compare their propositions. Comparison presupposes common yardsticks and common features: Just as the comparison of two phenomena with respect to length presupposes that one has concepts of units of length and that these concepts are applicable to both phenomena, so the comparison of propositions with respect to dis/agreement will presuppose that one has concepts of types of proposition and that these concepts are applicable to both sets of propositions. — If one has no concepts of proposition types, or if one applies them to propositions in relation to which they are out of place, then the comparison will be only an apparent one (pseudo-discussion) and the result a misunderstanding (pseudo dis/agreement).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Holmes, ‘The Path of the Law’, p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Peter Wessel Zapffe. Here quoted from Andenæs, Innfgring i rettsstudiet [introduction to the study of law], p. 113.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Freedom of Information Act (Act No. 69 of 19 June 1970), section 3 first paragraph.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Frankfurter, The Public and Its Government, p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Palme, Politikk — det er â ville noe [politics — that is the will to achieve something].

    Google Scholar 

  6. Clausewitz, Vom Kriege, p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Collingwood, ‘Modem Politics’, p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Osterud, ‘Er nasjonalstaten foreldet?’ [is the national state a thing of the past?], p. 352.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Osterud, Hva er nasjonalisme? [what is nationalism?], pp. 102 et seq.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Lord Moran, The Anatomy of Courage, p. 67

    Google Scholar 

  11. Various articles with this title in Stigen (ed.), Generasjoner i norsk filosofi [generations of Norwegian philosophy]; Deleuze/ Guattari, Qu’est-ce que la philosophie?

    Google Scholar 

  12. Schjelderup, ‘Filosofiens vesen’ [the essence of philosophy], p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Robinson, Plato’s Earlier Dialectic, p. 59: “[Questions of the What-is-x? form] is, perhaps, when unsupported by a context, the vaguest of all forms of question except an inarticulate grunt. It indicates less determinately than any other the sort of information the questioner wants” (my italics). — See also same writer, Definition, pp. 190, 192.

    Google Scholar 

  14. In accordance with normal language usage among lawyers I use the spelling “judgment” for a type of decision of the court. In all other cases I use the spelling “judgement”.

    Google Scholar 

  15. I use the word “fundamental” relative to the purpose and structuring of the present work. — A more complete survey of fundamental types of proposition is given in section II A below.

    Google Scholar 

  16. More precisely I could thus have used the formulation “the perspective of problem discussion and language decision”, but that would have been too cumbersome.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ross, On Law and Justice, e.g. p. 39 final paragraph.

    Google Scholar 

  18. I shall be returning in more detail to the said propositions in Ross in sections II B 5.2 (5)(b)(ii), 7.3.2 (1); C 2.1 (1), 2.1 (2)(a)(i), 2.3, 3.1 (2); and III 2.2.2 (3).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Compare also section III 2.2.2 (3)(c) below, at and in notes 43–45, where in another connection I mention some other writers’ answers to a critically reflexive mode of questioning concerning propositions about “what meaning is”.

    Google Scholar 

  20. In the text at the present note and throughout this work I use the term “academic subject” in the broad sense of the Scandinavian “fag” and the German “Fach”, i.e. I use it of crafts, professional subjects and academic disciplines. Further, I use the term “science” (1) in the broad sense of the Scandinavian “vitenskap” and the German “Wissenschaft”, i.e. to cover natural, social and human sciences, and (2) as an abbreviation for “activity one traditionally terms ”science“ in this broad sense” — that is, I neither presuppose nor lay down anything contentious through this concept of ‘science’.

    Google Scholar 

  21. I use the formulation “legal theory” in a broad sense, also of discussions that are traditionally designated “legal philosophy”.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Concerning the everyday-language orientation, see in addition e.g. sections II B 1 (3); 2; and III 1.

    Google Scholar 

  23. On the relationship between the presentation given in this work and the reader’s own reality, see further a retrospective treatment in-depth in Chapter IHV.

    Google Scholar 

  24. The word “or” I use throughout in the broad sense ‘either the one alternative, or the other alternative, or both alternatives’.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See section 5.1 above concerning sections II F (fused descriptive and normative propositions) and V (reconstructions and redefinitions).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Unless more special definition is explicitly stated or is clear from the context, I use “analysis and argumentation” as a derived variant of “language and argumentation”. There are two reasons for my use of this variant. First, I wish to point to a practically important specification: In relation to the broad area designated “language and argumentation”, “analysis” points to the sub-area of more reflected activity. Secondly, there is the consideration for effective communication of a major feature of the perspective and topic of the present work, namely the focusing of and on everyday language in contrast to artificial languages, including in particular logic and mathematics (section 5.1 above, introductory remarks, cf. the present section 5 in its entirety): To remind the reader of this major feature of the perspective and topic of the work, in a number of places I bring in the qualifier “formulated in everyday language”. Even though strictly speaking one might justify the formulation “language and argumentation formulated in everyday language”, such a formulation may at first glance provoke resistance (“language… formulated in… language” may at first glance look like three terms for the same thing) and may thus get in the way of comprehension. Therefore I link the qualifier “formulated in everyday language” to the formulation “analysis and argumentation”.

    Google Scholar 

  27. As the work proceeds, it will provide a basis for a retrospective treatment in-depth of the paragraph containing the present note, see Chapter IHV, in the second indent.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Is the author a realist?

    Google Scholar 

  29. Of a philosophical nature too, if one uses the designation “applied philosophy”.

    Google Scholar 

  30. What does the author believe science is?

    Google Scholar 

  31. On the theme of independence, see further in section 7 below; a brief specification in section II A 8 below; and a retrospective treatment in-depth, with further references, in Chapter IHV.

    Google Scholar 

  32. To take general philosophy as an example, and especially in relation to definition theory: Concepts formed on the basis of “falsificationism” (Popper) or “physicalism” (Quine) show themselves incapable of capturing the wealth of nuances, the internal coherence (system character and dynamics), the independence and the factual significance of the definition field of everyday language; see respectively sections II B 1 (4) and G 2, below.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Eng, S. (2003). Introduction. In: Analysis of Dis/Agreement — with particular reference to Law and Legal Theory. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 66. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0381-9_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0381-9_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6370-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0381-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics