Skip to main content

John Stuart Mill as a Theorist of Toleration

  • Chapter
Toleration, Neutrality and Democracy
  • 136 Accesses

Abstract

John Stuart Mill has not featured as prominently as one might expect in discussions of diversity and toleration, even as the author of On Liberty 1 There may be various reasons for this neglect. One reason may be the more general belief that utilitarianism is inherently unable to cope with these problems, presumably because any account of them in terms of utility seems to deny that they are problems at all, to deny that differences between the conceptions of the good held by competing groups resist translation into a common utilitarian calculus. This perceived inability on the part of utilitarianism is bolstered by the classical objection that utilitarianism does not offer sufficient guarantees that individuals or minorities will not be sacrificed to the majority’s well being whenever that sacrifice leads to greater general good. That utilitarians are insensitive to the interests of minorities is also coupled with the charge that utilitarian policy-makers are insensitive to their subjects’ beliefs; that the historic relations between utilitarianism and colonialism help explain a pernicious ‘Government House Utilitarianism’ (one might say ‘India House Utilitarianism’), where a utilitarian elite sharply distinguish between the demands of the utilitarian theory of the rulers and the committed practices of the ruled.2 Another reason for the specific exclusion of On Liberty from recent discussions of toleration may stem from the increasing emphasis on groups, rather than individuals, as the objects of toleration. Mill’s individualism, as classically expressed in On Liberty, may seem inadequate to deal with the problems of ‘multiculturalism’ and the situation of individuals in groups that provide them with their ‘conceptions of the good’.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. This statement is less true of the literature of toleration in the United Kingdom than it is of the same literature in the United States. See, especially, the anthologies produced by the Morrell Centre at the University of York: e.g. S. Mendus, ed., Justifying Toleration, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), J. Horton and S. Mendus, eds., Aspects of Toleration, (London: Methuen, 1985 ) and J. Horton and P. Nicholson, eds., Toleration: Theory and Practice, ( Aldershot: Avebury, 1992 ).

    Google Scholar 

  2. B. Williams, `A critique of utilitarianism’, Utilitarianism: For and Against, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), 75–150 at pp. 135–140, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), pp. 108–110 and `The point of view of the universe: Sidgwick and the ambitions of ethics’, Making Sense of Humanity, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 153171 at p. 166.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See, especially, W. Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 52–53. Perhaps the most significant and seriously considered rejection of Mill’s usefulness for problems of social conflict is John Rawls’ rejection of Mill’s `comprehensive liberalism’ in favour of a `political liberalism’ in his Political Liberalism, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), of which more below.

    Google Scholar 

  4. John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government, in Collected Works, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1963–1991), XIX, p. 546. All future references to the Collected Works will give the work’s title in parentheses followed by CW and the volume and page number.Ibid, pp. 376–379, 394–398, 415–420.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See also the notorious claim of On Liberty, CW XVIII, p. 224: “Despotism is a legitimate mode of government in dealing with barbarians, provided the end be their improvement, and the means justified by actually effecting that end.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. Representative Government, CW XIX, p. 549.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See, for example, F. R. Berger, Happiness, Justice and Freedom, ( Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984 ), p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  8. On Liberty, CW XVIII, pp. 274–275.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Raymond Williams notes this historical contribution in Culture and Society, (New York: Harper and Row, 1958), pp. 58–59. Mill, of course, means by `culture’ something closer to our notion of `cultivation’, for example, `self-culture’.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See, e.g., J. Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Peter Nidditch ed., (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), Book II, Chapter XXXIII “Of the Association of Ideas”, pp. 394–401.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, L.A. Selby-Bigge ed., (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1888), Book II, Part III, Section V, “Of the effects of Custom”, pp. 422–424. For political matters, see Tbid, Book III, Part II, Section 10, “Of the Objects of Allegiance”, pp. 555–557 and Hume, Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1987), “Of the Original Contract”, p. 474–475. For the form of this idea with which Mill probably was most familiar, see William Paley, The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy, Book I, Chapter V, cited by J.B. Schneewind in Sidgwick’s Ethics and Victorian Moral Philosophy, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), p. 124. I am indebted to Schneewind for this reference.

    Google Scholar 

  12. J. Mill, Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, (London: Longmans, Green, Reader and Dyer,1869), Volume I, pp. 380–381, p. 368.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid, John Stuart Mill’s editorial comments, Volume I, p. 407.

    Google Scholar 

  14. J. Mill, Analysis, John Stuart Mill’s editorial comments, Volume I, pp. 117–120. For moral and political matters, see A System of Logic, CW VIII, p. 777.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See e.g. Logic, CW VII, p. 564–565. Paul Feyerabend has, of course, drawn attention to Mill’s insistence on the importance of knowledge of the entire history of science for scientific investigation in`Introduction: proliferation and realism as methodological principles’ in his Realism, Rationalism and Scientific Method: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.), p. 140143 and Against Method, ( London: Verso, 1978 ), p. 47–48.

    Google Scholar 

  16. G.W. Smith, “Social Liberty and Free Agency”, in J.S. Mill on Liberty in Focus, J. Gray and G.W. Smith eds. (London: Routledge, 1991), 239–259 at pp. 254–255. See also, G.W. Smith, “J.S. Mill on Edger and Réville: An Episode in the Development of Mill’s Conception of Freedom”, Journal of the History of Ideas 41, 1980, reprinted in J. C. Wood, ed. John Stuart Mill: Critical Perspectives, ( London: Routledge, 1988 ) 550–566.

    Google Scholar 

  17. For language, see Logic, CW VII, p. 663; for tradition, see Ibid, p. 238, cited above, and “Coleridge”, CW X, 117–164 at pp. 119–120; for economic institutions, see Principles of Political Economy, CW II, pp. 240–244, for legal and political institutions, see Logic, CW VIII, pp. 911–912.

    Google Scholar 

  18. On Liberty, CW XVIII, p. 220. That the `tyranny of opinion’ is on the increase and possesses its own historical dynamic, see Ibid, p. 269, 227.

    Google Scholar 

  19. lbid, p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  20. For women and slaves, see, e.g., On the Subjection of Women, CW XXI, pp. 267–270.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The Negro Question’, CW XXI, 85–96 at p. 93.

    Google Scholar 

  22. On Liberty, CW XVIII, p. 241.

    Google Scholar 

  23. They ask themselves, what is suitable to my position? what is usually done by persons of my station and pecuniary circumstances? or (worse still) what is usually done by persons of a station and circumstances superior to mine?“, Ibid, p. 264.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid, pp. 284–285, 290.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid, pp. 256–257.

    Google Scholar 

  26. For the former see, Representative Government, CW XIX, p. 506, and p. 476. For the latter see, e.g., On Liberty, CW XVIII p. 269.

    Google Scholar 

  27. All that has been said of the importance of individuality of character, and diversity in opinions and modes of conduct, involves, as of the same unspeakable importance, diversity of education.“, tbid, pp. 302–303.

    Google Scholar 

  28. This recommendation has obvious parallels with Mill’s suggestion that competing socialist cooperatives may be the solution to the problems of class power, where `class’ is construed in a narrow economic sense. See “Chapters on Socialism”, CW V, 703–756 at pp. 739–748.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Representative Government, CW XIX, pp. 546–547.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid, pp. 549–550.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Mill declares: a “moral or human interest” in nature, art, poetry, history and “the ways of mankind past and present, and their prospects in the future” to be chief among the sources of happiness. Utilitarianism,CW X, pp. 215–216

    Google Scholar 

  32. it is a personal injustice to withhold from anyone, unless for the prevention of greater evils, the33 Lynn Zastoupil, the only scholar to make an exhaustive investigation of the India House collection of Mill’s dispatches, has drawn on those dispatches to show that Mill’s career with the company is marked by an increased insistence on sensitivity to native customs and native opinion, in contrast with his father’s hostility and indifference to those aspects of Indian life. See Lynn Zastoupil, J.S. Mill and India. ( Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994 ).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Zastoupil, J.S. Mill, pp. 42–46. For Mill’s later views, see On Liberty, CW XVIII, pp. 240–241, note, in which the connection between toleration and liberty is emphasized: “I desire to call attention to the fact, that a man who has been deemed fit to fill a high office in the government of this country, under a liberal Ministry, maintains the doctrine that all who do not believe in the divinity of Christ are beyond the pale of toleration. Who, after this imbecile display, can indulge the illusion that religious persecution has passed away, never to return?”

    Google Scholar 

  34. The East India Company’s Charter’, CW XXX, 31–74 at p. 49.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Representative Government, CW XIX, p. 568–569.

    Google Scholar 

  36. For in the subject community also there are oppressors and oppressed; powerful individuals or classes, and slaves prostrate before them; and it is the former, not the latter, who have the means of access to the English public.“, Representative Government, CW XIX, p. 572.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid, CW XIX, p. 571.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Representative Government, CW XIX, pp. 570–571. `Minute on the Black Act’, CW XXX, 11–16 at pp. 14–15.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Representative Government, CW XIX, p. 570.

    Google Scholar 

  40. In England, the experts of the Examiner’s Office, of which Mill eventually became the head, guided the decisions of the Court of Directors, who in turn proposed policies to the Board of Control, which had a veto over policies it considered unwise. Policies produced through this complex process of revision eventually were eventually sent, as despatches, to the government in India, both as comments on the Indian government’s previous actions and as guides to its future action.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Representative Government, CW XIX, p. 447.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Recognition“, m A. Gutmann, ed., Multiculturalism, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994) 25–74. Gutmann herself is an exception to the above claims about `liberal neutrality’. See, e.g., A. Gutmann, ”Why Go to School?“ in A. Sen and B. Williams, eds. Utilitarianism and Beyond. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 261–278, as is J. Raz, The Morality of Freedom, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986) and `Multiculturalism: A Liberal Perspective’, Dissent, Winter, (1994), 67–79.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid, pp. 141–143.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid, p. 169 and p. 143, respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid, p. 139.

    Google Scholar 

  47. bid, p. xxi.

    Google Scholar 

  48. In, of course, Mill’s sense of `equal access’, which famously does not mean, at least not necessarily,equal participation in terns of voting.

    Google Scholar 

  49. The example of Tennessee fundamentalists is from A. Gutman, “Undemocratic Education”, in Nancy L.. Rosenblum, ed.,Liberalism and the Moral Life, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 71–88 at pp. 81–82. The Amish are discussed in W. Kymlicka, Multicultural, p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  50. John Gray notes this in Enlightenment’s Wake, (London: Routledge, 1995), p. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See On Liberty, CW XVIII, pp. 301–302, Principles, CW III, p. 947.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Finlay, G. (2003). John Stuart Mill as a Theorist of Toleration. In: Castiglione, D., McKinnon, C. (eds) Toleration, Neutrality and Democracy. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0241-6_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0241-6_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6492-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0241-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics