Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Islamic Philosophy and Occidental Phenomenology in Dialogue ((IPOP,volume 1))

Abstract

The De Anima treatise (Kitāb al-nafs) of Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā, 980–1037) has important implications for the disputes over the interpretation of Aristotle’s compelling work Πєρì \(\psi \upsilon \chi \hat \eta \varsigma \) (peri psuchēs, De Anima). It also has significant implications regarding the course of development of Modern European philosophy and the unfolding of contemporary debates of the philosophy of mind and phenomenology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. After all, technē poiētikē reveals a capacity to bring something into being.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Franz Brentano, “Noûs Poiētikos: Survey of Earlier Interpretations,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995, p. 316.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., pp. 331–32.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., p. 330.

    Google Scholar 

  5. The reader may refer to: Aristotle, Metaphysics, W. D. Ross (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1924.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Brentano, “Noûs Poiētikos: Survey of Earlier Interpretations,” pp. 326–28.

    Google Scholar 

  7. K. V. Wilkes, “Psuchē versus the Mind,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.) Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., pp. 115–16.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Martha C. Nussbaum, Hilary Putnam, “Changing Aristotle’s Mind,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995 ), pp. 51–52.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  10. Richard Sorabji, “Intentionality and Physiological Processes: Aristotle’s Theory of Sense-Perception,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995, p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. 211.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Aristotle, De Anima, D. W. Hamlyn (trans.) Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993, p. 104. For the Greek text refer to: Aristotle, Πєρì ψυχης,. W. D. Ross (ed.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961. Hereafter the translated text will be designated as De Anima and the Greek edition as Πєρì ψυχης. Also refer to: Aristotle, On the Soul Parva Naturalia on Breath, W. S. Hett, (trans.) Loeb Classical Library No. 288, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Aristotle, De Anima, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Sorabji, “Intentionality and Physiological Processes,” p. 224.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., pp. 224–25.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Sorabji’s resistance of the theoretical inclinations that adopt the concept of intentionality in the interpretation of Aristotle’s Πєρì ψυχης is also vehemently revealed in: Richard Sorabji, “From Aristotle to Brentano: the Development of the Concept of Intentionality,” in Festschrift fur A. C. Lloyd: on the Aristotelian Tradition, H. Blumenthal and H. Robinson (eds.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Sorabji, “Intentionality and Physiological Processes,” p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Myles F. Bumyeat, “Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible?,” in Essays on Aristotle’s De Anima, Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.) Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995, pp. 1516.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., pp. 17–18.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., pp. 18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., pp. 21–22.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., pp. 23–24. It is worthy to note herein that the difficulties facing Aristotle’s model of vision were transgressed by the Optics (Kitāb āb al-mānaẓir, De aspectibus) of Alhazen (Ibn al-Haytham, 965–1039) which led to the emergence of the perspectiva naturalis tradition in science and the perspectiva artiftcialis tradition in art. See: The Optics of Ibn al-Haytham, Books I–III, On Direct Vision, 2 vols., A. I. Sabra (trans.), London: Warburg Institute, University of London, 1989; Kitāb al-manāẓir, A. I. Sabra (ed.) Kuwait: National Council for Culture, Arts & Letters, 1983; Opticae thesaurus Alhazeni, Friedrich Risner (ed.), Basel, 1572.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Wilkes, “Psuchē versus the Mind,” pp. 111–12.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Wilkes also holds that Descartes’ “I” describes a solipsistic passive mode of being in contrast with Aristotle’s psuchē which ethically seeks eudaimonia as its highest good, given that being good entails doing something good. Unlike the Cartesian mind which describes an “inner space” that is isolated somehow from the world which is open to destructibility, Aristotle’s “soul” is active from an ethical standpoint and involved in the affairs of the polis and the attends to the matters of philia. Ibid., p. 118–19.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Charles H. Khan, “Aristotle on Thinking,” in Essays on Aristotle ‘s De Anima, eds. Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995, p. 363.

    Google Scholar 

  28. In an appeal to Martin Heidegger’s reading of Aristotle William McNeil holds that τò τί ήν єїναι is primary ousia, which is understood of being yet applied herein to the understanding of the soul. See: William McNeil, The Glance of the Eye: Heidegger, Aristotle, and the Ends of Theory, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999, p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Dag Nikolaus Hasse, Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West: The Formation of a Peripatetic Philosophy of the Soul 1160–1300, London: The Warburg Institute, 2000, p. v.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., pp. v, 1. Of those deeply influenced by Avicenna’s De Anima, one could mention Dominicus Gundissalinus, John Blund, Michael Scot, Roland of Cremona, William of Auvergne, Jean de la Rochelle, Petrus Hispanus Portugalensis, Albertus Magnus, and Thomas Aquinas. Moreover, Avicenna’s ontology attests to the rise of phenomenological dimensions in ontology, that are akin to what we find in Heidegger’s thought about being, which depart from the confines of Aristotle’s ousiology. Regarding our views viz. this issue, see: Nader El-Bizri, The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger Binghamton, N.Y.: Global Publications SUNY, 2000, Introduction and chapters 4 and 5; Nader El-Bizri, “Avicenna and Essentialism,” Review of Metaphysics, vol. 54 (June 2001), pp. 533–58.

    Google Scholar 

  31. As Jean-Paul Sartre holds, the fundamental idea of Husserl is exemplified in accounting for the necessity of consciousness to exist as a consciousness of what is other than the self, a necessity that is given the name ‘intentionality.’ See: Jean-Paul Sartre, Situations Philosophiques, Paris: Gallimard, 1990, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  32. For some brief remarks on the influence of Brentano on Husserl, refer to: Joseph Kockelmans, Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenology, West Lafayette, IN: Purdue University Press, 1994, pp. 2, 31–33, 40, 53–54, 92, 158.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Edmund Husserl, Idées directrices pour une phénoménologie, Ideen-I, Paul Ricoeur (trans.), Paris: Editions Gallimard, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Jaakko Hintikka, “The Phenomenological Dimension,” in The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Barry Smith and David Woodruff Smith (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995, p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Hans Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (trans.), 2nd ed., London: Sheed & Ward, 1989, p. 244.

    Google Scholar 

  36. In this sense, phenomenology would entail the showing of what self-shows itself in appearing, in so far that it self-shows itself as it is itself.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la Perception (Paris: Editions Gallimard, 1945), p. iii; Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. Joan Stambaugh, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996, § 7.

    Google Scholar 

  38. The Glance of the Eye, p. 336.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Rudolf Bernet, Iso Kern, and Eduard Marbach (eds.), An Introduction to Husserlian Phenomenology Evanston IL: Northwestern university Press, 1993, p. 66 — Erste Philosophie, vol. 2, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, David Can (trans.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1970. Referred to in this chapter hereafter as Krisis.

    Google Scholar 

  41. René Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, John Cottingham (trans.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Our approach to Avicenna’s De Anima belongs to a broad attempt to hermeneutically reconstruct what we take to be the occluded other tradition which is veiled within the multi-layered folds of the history of European philosophy in view of unconcealing its hidden philosophical possibilities. It is in this regard that we consider this chapter to be commensurate with other investigations we have conducted elsewhere: “Avicenna and Essentialism,” Review of Metaphysics, vol. 54 (June 2001), pp. 533–58; The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger; “Reason and the ‘Critique of Arabic Heritage’,” in al-Hayat, Horizon Supplement, Issue 13497, (February 2000), p. 18; “Avicenna and Heidegger’s Critique of the History of Metaphysics,” in al-Hayat, Horizon Supplement, Issue 13134 (February 1999), p. E.

    Google Scholar 

  43. This argument appears in: Kitāb al-Shifā’, Tabīīyyāt, Kitāb al-Nafs (De Anima), I. Madkour, G. Anawati, S. Zayed (eds.) Cairo: al-hay’a al-mişriyya al= āmma lil-kitāb bnbn, 1975, p. 13, lines 9–20; Avicenna’s De Anima (Arabic Text), F. Rahman (ed.) London: Oxford University Press, 1959, p. 16; L. E. Goodman, Avicenna, London: Routledge, 1992, pp. 155–56. This argument and the other passages that we have translated from Arabic do also partly appear in our book: The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger, Chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West, pp. 82–83.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Avicenna’s De Anima, F. Rahman (ed.) London: Oxford University Press, 1959, 1.1; afterwards as: De Anima.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West, p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  47. De Anima, preface p.1.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Kitāb al-Najāt, Majid Fakhry (ed.), Beirut: dār al-‘āfāq al jadīda, 1985, pp. 222–23.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid., pp. 224, 226, 230.

    Google Scholar 

  50. De Anima V:7, pp. 250–252,253–254.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., p. 255.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid, p. 256.

    Google Scholar 

  53. al-Najāt, pp. 330, 332.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Kitāb al-Ishārāt wal-Tanbīhāt (Livre des Directives et Remarques), A. -M. Goichon (trans.) Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1951, III:1.

    Google Scholar 

  55. For the mystic consideration of the nafs and its spiritual journeying see: Henri Corbin, Avicenne et Le Récit Visionnaire, Tehran: Société des Monuments Nationaux de l’Iran, 1954; August Mehren, Traités Mystiques d’Avicenne, Amsterdam: Philo Press, 1979; The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger, chapter 7.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Avicenna Latinus (Liber De Anima, I-V), Van Riet Simone (trans.) Leiden: Brill, 1972, pp. 32*-35*.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid., pp.36*-37*.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Peter Heath. Allegory and Philosophy in Avicenna, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania, 1992, p. 56; Michael Marmura, “Avicenna’s ‘Flying Man’ in Context,” The Monist 69, 3 (1986) pp. 383–95.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Avicenna Latinus, p.37*.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., pp. 46*-47*.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., pp. 72*-73*.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Refer to the allusion to the views of Herbert Spiegelberg, in “Intentionen und Intentionalität” (1936); Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West, p. 127; Goodman, Avicenna, pp. 155–58.

    Google Scholar 

  63. al-Ishārāt wal-Tanbīhāt, pp. 317, 322, 323;, pp. 202, 206–07.

    Google Scholar 

  64. al-Najāt, pp. 197, 198.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Ibid., p. 200. One ought to add herein that the Latin terms, intentio and intentions, may not be respectively exclusive renditions for the Arabic terms: ma c (meaning) and ma c nāī (meanings). These Latin terms could also act as valid renderings of the Arabic term qaşd (“what is meant”: the sense that is sought), and more so for the terms nīyya (intention) and nīyyāt (intentions).

    Google Scholar 

  66. One could also say, like Hasse, that a third observer, a girl who accompanies the shepherd, may observe that the sheep trusts the shepherd, and the cause for this is the friendliness of the shepherd himself. Similarly, an opposite intention (by empathy) may be observed by the same third observer in the fear of the sheep from the wolf and the cause for this is the hostility of the predator wolf itself. Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West, p. 136.

    Google Scholar 

  67. al-Najāt, p. 201. The faculty of wahm is also a faculty of judgment (hukm). As Hasse holds, the faculty of wahm does with intentions (or what he refers to as “connotational attributes”) what the external senses do with sense data: perceiving and passing judgment about them. See: Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West, p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Hasse renders ma c ānī as “connotational attributes” instead of “intentions” in an attempt to polemically avoid in an appeal to intentionality. See: Avicenna’s De Anima in the Latin West, p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  69. In a contemporary and model appeal to an example about the sheep and the wolf similar to what is attested in the Latin commentaries on Avicenna, one encounters a discussion of what appears as being Avicenna’s conceptions of intentionality in the works of Fernando Gil and Frederick Adams. See: Fernando Gil, La Conviction, Paris: Flammarion, 2000, pp. 76–81; Frederick Adams, “Causal Contents,” in Dretske and his Critics, B. McLaughlin (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1991, p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

  70. al-Najāt, Met. I, p. 239–242.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Parviz Morewedge, Essays in Islamic Philosophy, Theology, and Mysticism, Oneonta: SUNY, 1995, pp. 139–40.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ibid., pp. 142–44, 150–53, 157–159, 169.

    Google Scholar 

  73. The expression “tawahhum” designates what has wahm. This term may be derived from the root terms “wahm” or “hamm” (a worry about a concrete practical situation). Al-wahm itself has the contemporary meaning of imaginative illusions or myths (khurāfāt). However, with Avicenna, “wahm” is not a myth or illusion, nor is it linked to the term “hamm” as concemful worry. The use of the term “wahm,” in the context of our discussion, is restricted to the classical Arabic philosophical usage, as an inner sense faculty. 73 After all, technē poiētikē reveals a capacity to bring something into being.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

El-Bizri, N. (2003). Avicenna’s de Anima: Between Aristotle and Husserl. In: Tymieniecka, AT. (eds) The Passions of the Soul in the Metamorphosis of Becoming. Islamic Philosophy and Occidental Phenomenology in Dialogue, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0229-4_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0229-4_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6359-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0229-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics