Skip to main content

Enthusiasm and the Light Within

  • Chapter
Henry More, 1614–1687

Abstract

As we saw in More’s poetic allegory of the spiritual journey in his Poems, he had first defined ‘Enthusiasm’ in terms reminiscent of the spiritual acceptance of a ‘false light’ described in the Theologia Germanica as an almost inevitable temptation upon the path of spiritual development, or as he later put it, a “full but false persuasion that in a man that he is inspired”.1 For More this was the result of the ‘natural’ consciousness of body and self possessing the mind — a temptation which was furthered by the determinism and ‘unfelt hypocrisy’ of orthodox Calvinism.2 From this perspective, Enthusiasm was one important aspect of the negative delusive forces assailing the soul in quest of union with God. For this reason in his later theological works More uses the concept of Enthusiasm alongside that of Atheism and Roman Catholicism as three interrelated expressions of the ‘mystery of iniquity’ assailing both the individual and the Church.3

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. ET (1656): 2.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Psychozoia“, iii,10–22; and TG (1854), xl, and see below.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See More, GMG, V,viii-xii; VI,xii-xviii; VIl,xvii; Mystery of Iniquity, I,xi ff.; and TW (1708), An Alphabetical Table: 834: “Antichristianism”, and below.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Vaughan (1622–1666) was the brother of the poet, Henry Vaughan. See A. Rudrum (ed.), Works of Thomas Vaughan (1984): 7–12. On More’s debate with Vaughan, see Fouke, Enthusiastical Concerns: 53 ff. and A. Miller Guinsburg, “Henry More, Thomas Vaughan and the late Renaissance Magical Tradition”, Ambix, 27 (1980): 36–58; F.L. Burnham, “The More-Vaughan Controversy: the Revolt against Philosophical Enthusiasm”, J.H.I., 35 (1975): 33–49; N.I. Brann, “The Conflict between Reason and Magic in Seventeenth Century England. A Case Study on the Vaughan-More Debate”, H.L.Q., 43 (1980): 103–126; and L. Mulligan, “’Reason’, `Right Reason’, and `Revelation’ in midseventeenth-century England”, in Vickers (ed.), Occult and Scientific Mentalities in the Renaissance (1984): 375–401; and below. Vaughan appears to have been on the fringes of those alchemists associated with Robert Boyle, but no one has yet found any direct connection between them. It is highly unlikely Boyle would have approved of Vaughan’s intemperate language, or for that matter, his alleged drunkenness.

    Google Scholar 

  5. On the widespread abusive use of the term, see M. Heyd, “The Reaction against Enthusiasm in the Seventeenth Century: Towards an Integrative Approach” Journal of Modern History 53 (1981): 25880. See also, for example, Meric Casaubon, Treatise concerning Enthusiasme (1656): 52–4, 110–119 and 125–130, whose more conservative account, putting Platonists and Cartesians into this category, provides a useful contrast to More’s.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Lawrence Pincipe, The Aspiring Adept: Robert Boyle and his Alchemical Quest. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998 ). The apparent personal connection between Vaughan and Boyle needs further elucidation.

    Google Scholar 

  7. E. Philalethes, The Man-Mouse taken in a Trap and Tortur’d to Death for Gnawing the Margins of Eugenius Philalethes (1650). Vaughan was later used as a `type’ of enthusiasm by Samuel Butler and Jonathan Swift. See Rudrum, Works (1984): 27–30.

    Google Scholar 

  8. More, Second Lash, in ET: 174–5.

    Google Scholar 

  9. More is referring to his PP.

    Google Scholar 

  10. As Walker points out, Spiritual and Demonic Magic (1975): 52 and 75 ff., there were significant tensions within Renaissance Platonism between a fascination for theurgy and magical practices, whether for specific cures or for illumination, and a denial of the necessity or legality of such practices. In Agrippa, Vaughan’s avowed master, this tension can be clearly see (Ibid, 54–5, and 90–1). While More is unequivocally anti-magical, Vaughan follows his master in apologising for his earlier magical concerns, in Euphrates (1655), `To the Reader’.

    Google Scholar 

  11. As does Burnham, “More-Vaughan”: 33–49. However, N. Brann, “Conflict”: 104, who remarks that the debate can best be viewed as “more of a fraternal rivalry within the same family than as a combat between spokesmen of radically divergent world views” seems to take the opposing view too far.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See the discussion below, and the comments in A. Miller Guinsburg, “Henry More, Thomas Vaughan”: 45.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Compare for example, More’s use of Agrippa, PP: 364, and Vaughan’s defence of the latter, Anthroposophia Theomagica (1650): 33–4, and comment on 50: “He indeed is my Author, and next to God I owe all that I have unto him.”

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Miller Guinsburg, “Henry More, Thomas Vaughan”:41.

    Google Scholar 

  15. More, Psychozoia ii-iii, Psychathanasia, I,iii; Vaughan, Lumen de Lumine (1651): 225.

    Google Scholar 

  16. More, Psychozoia iii,69–71; Vaughan, Lumen de Lumine (1651): 13–15.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Vaughan, Anthroposophia Theomagica (1651): 5.

    Google Scholar 

  18. More, Second Lash, in ET: 175, cited above.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 10.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Fouke, Enthusiastical Concerns, chapter 4; C.H. Josten, “A Translation of John Dee’s Monas Heiroglyphica (Antwerp, 1564), with an Introduction and Annotations.” Ambix, 12 (1964): 100–4; and also M. Eliade, The Forge and the Crucible (1978): 225–7.

    Google Scholar 

  21. More, “Psychozoia” ii,9–12, and the “Interpretation Generall” in PP, under le’; and see Plotinus, IV,ii,9, which More explains, PP: 353–4.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 79; and see also Euphrates (1655): 23.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Vaughan, Lumen de Lumine (1651): 21 and 68 ff.; and Pincipe, Aspiring Adept. See also Eliade, Forge: 154.

    Google Scholar 

  24. More, Second Lash, in ET: 218. More explicitly rejects a real primal matter, but it is clear that he accepted the idea of an abstract principle representing the potentiality of material existence, which preexisted the real `atomic’ matter from which bodies were formed (by the ‘Spirit of Nature). See “Psychozoia”, ii,9; “Psychathanasia”, I.ii,54; DP,12–16; and CC, The Philosophical Cabbala i,1–3; and the discussion below.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See Vaughan, Anima Magica Abscondita (1650): 51–3, and More’s reaction in Observations (1650): 55 and 59–61. More’s interpretation of Plotinus is necessarily selective: see for instance Plotinus, IV,iv,36 and IV,iv,40, which would lend credence to Vaughan’s view rather than More’s. On More and Plotinus, see above.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Euphrates (1655): 17.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Plato, Timaeus, 31b ff, and 69c ff., and Philebus, 29e. The image is also Stoic.

    Google Scholar 

  28. More, Second Lash, in ET: 204–5.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 65; and see also his Euphrates (1655): 36–9.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 35. On Vaughan’s alchemical prowess, and claims to have discovered the cosmic `menstruum’, see Rudrum, Works (1984): 13. More’s more poetic use of such `miraculous incredible symbols’ can be seen in his treatment of Copernicanism in his “Psychathanasia”, III,iii; and in his poem “Circulatio Sanguinis” (OP OM (vol.3, 1679): 751–753) discussed above.

    Google Scholar 

  31. The doctrine is Stoic in origin, though it is clear More’s source is Plotinus, V,ix,9; II,ii,2; and II,iii,17. Plotinus is referring back to Plato, Timaeus, 29a ff. See the more explicit discussion in Cudworth, TIS (1687): 158–9, and More’s interpretation, PP: 345–6.

    Google Scholar 

  32. PP: 345–6; and Plotinus, III,11,2.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See “Psychozoia”, ii,7–9, and CC, The Philosophical Cabbala., i,1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  34. More, Second Lash, in ET: 269–70; and see the discussion below, next chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Psychozoia, i,41–47; and IS, III,xii,l-6; and see the discussion below, next chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 182; and see also Euphrates (1655): 16–8.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 180.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Vaughan, Man-Mouse Taken (1650): 104–6; and see also Euphrates (1655): 67–8.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Second Wash (1651): 181; and see also Euphrates (1655): 18 and p.93.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See for instance, ET.: 51.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See Euphrates (1655): 17, cited above.

    Google Scholar 

  42. More, Observations (1650): 6; and Second Lash, in ET: 261–6.

    Google Scholar 

  43. This quarrel over the soul touches upon the `learned ministry’ debate. For Vaughan by implication was attacking the scholastic curriculum, even while protesting his faithfulness to Oxford. See Anthroposophia Theomagica (1650), “To the Reader”, and see Rudrum, Works (1984): 2–6.

    Google Scholar 

  44. More, Second Lash, in ET: 259.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Anthroposophia Theomagica (1650): 7.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Man-Mouse Caught (1651): 76–7.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See Lumen de Lumine (1651): 251–3, and the engraved plate facing p.22.

    Google Scholar 

  48. More is never very consistent with his use of the term `reason’. For he considers it to be the expression of a `middle life’ in the soul, which must choose between becoming `immersed’ in the `animal’ or `divine Life’. It appears from this that he means two things by the word, depending on its context - a divine intellectual principle in man, and a discursive faculty, which he places with the imagination in the ‘middle part’ of the soul. Compare the definition in GMG, II,xi,1 with the treatment of ‘Right Reason’ (as a successive copy of the Logos) in EE, II,iii,3; II,iv,6; II,v,4–7; and II,ix,14–6.

    Google Scholar 

  49. More, PP: 302, and see above.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Op.cit, in ET: 177.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See below, Chapter, on More’s similar judgement of the natural philosophy of John Webster.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Second Lash, in ET: 178.

    Google Scholar 

  53. See Vaughan, Second Wash (1651), dedicatory poem “by H.M., Oxon”, and “To the Reader”, replying to More, Second Lash, in ET: 178–84.

    Google Scholar 

  54. See G.H. Williams, Radical Reformation (1962): 363 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  55. See Vaughan, Second Wash (1651): 10 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  56. See below, especially Chapters 11 and 12.

    Google Scholar 

  57. TG: xl.

    Google Scholar 

  58. TG:: 134–5. Compare More, ET: sig.A5 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  59. See the title: Enthusiasmus Triumphatus, or, a discourse of the nature, causes, kinds and cure of Enthusiasm (1656), and Mastix his Letter, in Ibid: 309 ff..

    Google Scholar 

  60. See for example Nicolson: 100, and 378 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  61. I emphasise More’s ambivalence here, as the evidence that he became `more sympathetic’ to Boehme is somewhat entangled with Anne Conway’s renewed interest in the latter after Elizabeth Foxcroft came to live with her (pace Hutton, “More and Boehme” in Hutton). On Boehme’s influence in contemporary England, see M. Bailey, Milton and Jacob Boehme (1914); Jones, Spiritual Reformers (1928): 208 ff.; and Thune, The Behmenists and the Philadelphians (1948).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Mastix his Letter, in ET: 275.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Nicolson: 306.

    Google Scholar 

  64. This was written in English in 1670, according to the PG, but is known only in the Latin version published in the OP OM (tom.2, 1679): 529 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Teutonica Censura, Preface, sect.22, in OP OM. (tom.2, 1679): 535. See also DD: 465–470.

    Google Scholar 

  66. ET: 42–3; compare Teutonicae Censura, Quaestio 1, OP OM (tom.2, 1679): 538–40. See also More on Boehme’s claim to understand the language of Nature, DD: 461–3.

    Google Scholar 

  67. See also Teutonica Censura (1679), Quaestio 1, sect.13–15, OP OM. (tom. 2, 1679 ): 538–9.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Op.cit (1656): 48.

    Google Scholar 

  69. DD: 469–70.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Op.cit, Quaestio 2, sect.7 and 9, in OP OM (tom.2, 1679): 541–2. See also DD: 467.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Teutonica Censura, sect. 4–5, in OP OM (tom.2, 1679): 541.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Teutonica Censura, Quaestio 3, sect.2 ff., in OP OM (tom. 2, 1679 ): 542–3.

    Google Scholar 

  73. See DD: 468–70, where More effectively excuses the Behmenists from being the great danger to the world they appeared to be: 470: “God does notable execution upon the dead Formality and Carnality of Christendom by these zealous Evangelists of an internal Saviour.”

    Google Scholar 

  74. GMG: VIII xii 1–2. This passage could serve as a prose commentary on More’s description of Glaucis in “Psychozoia” (1647): ii 87 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  75. See below, and for example, GMG: VI xii-xiii.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See TG: xl.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See Hamilton, Family of Love (1981). The works of Niclaes were all translated into English, though by the time More was writing the sect had practically disappeared in England, the name `Familist’ being then mainly applied to the Quakers. See for example, H. Hallywell, An Account of Familism as it is Revived and Propagated by the Quakers (1673). After 1668 More was particularly concerned with denouncing Niclaes because of his apparent popularity with Anne Conway and her companion, Elizabeth Foxcroft. See Nicolson: 304.

    Google Scholar 

  78. See Hamilton, op.cit (1981): 26 ff., and 55–61; and More, GMG: VI xii 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Hamilton, op.cit (1981): 50–1; More, GMG: VI xii 3–5; and ET: 34–5.

    Google Scholar 

  80. GMG: V viii 6 and VI xii 1–3, and passim.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Nicolson: 297. Elizabeth Foxcroft was Benjamin Whichcote’s sister, and appears to have first introduced Anne Conway to the Quakers. She was in touch with the Quaker, Henry Bromley, in 1666. In a letter from him (Ibid: 278–80) he speaks respectfully of Anne Conway as a person already in sympathy with the Friends (in Nov.1666). This suggests that Anne first encountered them before 1670. On September 15, 1670, More mentions George Keith in a letter to her as though he was already a familiar figure to both of them. So the beginning of Quaker influence on Anne Conway predates the arrival of van Helmont at Ragley (late 1670), by some years. Versus Coudert, “A Quaker-Kabbalist Controversy: George Fox’s Reaction to Francis Mercurius Van Helmont”, J.W.C.I. 39 (1976): 179. See Nicolson: 307.

    Google Scholar 

  82. See GMG: VI xiv-xvii; and DD: 565 ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Crocker, R. (2003). Enthusiasm and the Light Within. In: Henry More, 1614–1687. International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées, vol 185. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0217-1_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0217-1_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6373-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0217-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics