Skip to main content

What is “Logical” in Husserl’s Logical Investigations? The Copenhagen Interpretation

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 164))

Abstract

In Wim Wenders’s 1987 film Himmel Über Berlin (Wings of Desire in the English subtitle version), an angel moves silently among mortals, listening to their thoughts as they read in the Berlin public library. In this spirit, assume that Husserl is listening to our readings today of his Logical Investigations (1900–01).1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. I shall quote from J. N. Findlay’s 1970 English translation, Logical Investigations (Volumes One and Two), of the German edition which combines the first edition of 1900–01 with revisions in the second edition of 1913 and revisions of the Sixth Investigation in the edition of 1920.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See in particular D. Willard, Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge: A Study of Husserl’s Early Philosophy, Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1984; J.N. Mohanty, “The development of Husserl’s thought.” (In B. Smith and D. W. Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995); and C. O. Hill and G. E Rosado Haddock (eds.), Husserl or Frege? Meaning, Objectivity, and Mathematics, Chicago and La Salle: Open Court, Cams Publishing Company, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  3. J. Hintikka, Knowledge and Belief, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1962; Models and Modalities, Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  4. However, see the line of argument in D. W. SMITH, “Intentionality Naturalized?” (In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud, and J.-M. Roy (eds.), Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science,Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1999) and other essays in the same volume.

    Google Scholar 

  5. B. Bolzano, Theory of Science: Attempt at a Detailed and in the main Novel Exposition of Logic With Constant Attention to Earlier Authors. Edited and translated (selections) by R. George,Berkeley: University ofCalifomia Press, 1972. German original, 1837. See also P. SlMOxs, “Bolzano, Tarski, and the limits of logic”, In P. Simons, Philosophy and Logic in Central Europe from Bolzano to Tarski: Selected Essays. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  6. B. Smith, “Logic and Formal Ontology”, in J. N. Mohanty and W. McKenna (eds.), Husserl’s Phenomenology: A Textbook,Lanham: University Press of America, 1989, 29–67, aptly discusses many of the issues to follow. However, I want to stress how three distinct disciplines are related: formal logic, formal ontology, and (if you will, formal) phenomenology.

    Google Scholar 

  7. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason. Transi. and edited by P. Guyer and A. W. Wood, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997, 1998. German original, 1781, revised 1787.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See W. v. O. QUINE, Methods of Logic, New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1950, 1959; Philosophy of Logic, Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1970; Pursuit of Truth, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1992, 1990; From Stimulus to Science, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  9. E. Husserl, Ideas pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and a Phenomenological Philosophy, First Book: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology,translated by W. R. Boyce Gibson, London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., and New York: Humanities Press, Inc., 1969. First English edition, 1931; German original, first published in 1913. Called Ideas I.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See E. Husserl, Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics. Translated by D. Willard, Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1994. Original German texts here gathered, from 1890–1901; and the essays in C. O. Hill and G. E. Rosado Haddock, Husserl or Frege?,on the connections and differences between Husserl, Cantor, Frege, and others in late 19th century foundations of mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Extending Husserlian part/whole theory, P. Simons, Parts,Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987, pursues nonextensional mereology, which contrasts with set theory and with extensional mereology (where wholes are treated extensionally, rather like sets without braces). See also K. Fine, “Part-whole”, in B. Smith and D. W. Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995, reflecting on Husserl’s part-whole theory.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See D. W. Smith and R. Mcintyre, Husserl and Intentionality: A Study of Mind, Meaning, and Language, Dordrect: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1982. Now from Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht and Boston, Chapter V on horizon. The horizon of an experience includes only “motivated” possibilities, those with appropriate probability given what is prescribed by the content or noema of the experience.

    Google Scholar 

  13. For an illuminating assessment of Husserl’s ideal of a theory of manifolds, see C. O. Hill, “Husserl’s Mannigfaltigkeitslehre”,in C. O. Hill and G.E. Rosado Haddock, Husserl or Frege?

    Google Scholar 

  14. Husserl later used ’Mannigfaltigkeit’ for a more special purpose when launching his notion of “horizon”. See D. W. Smith and R. Mcintyre, Husserl and Intentionality,Chapter V.

    Google Scholar 

  15. R. Tieszen and P. Martin-La have both made this observation to me in discussion.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See P. Simons, Parts,distinguishing Husserlian part theory from extensional mereology, the latter akin to extensional set theory.

    Google Scholar 

  17. For details see my reconstruction of Husserl’s ontology in D. W. Smith, “Mind and body”, in B. Smith and D. W. Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl,Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995; and D.W. Smith, “`Pure’ Logic, Ontology, and Phenomenology”, in Revue internationale de philosophie,2001, issue edited by D. Fellesdal.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See A. Tarski, “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages”, in A. Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics,Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956. Second edition. Indianapolis: Hacket, 1983. Essay originally published in Polish, 1933; in German translation, 1936; and “The Semantic Conception of Truth”, in L. Linsky (ed.), Semantics and the Philosophy of Language. Urbana: The University of Illinois Press, 1952, 1964. Original, 1944, in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4.

    Google Scholar 

  19. The details are reconstructed in D.W. Smith and R. Mcintyre, Husserl and Intentionality. What is new here is the way in which that analysis fits into the overall system of Husserl’s Logical Investigations.

    Google Scholar 

  20. This is especially clear in the case of indexical forms of awareness. See D.W. Smith, The Circle of Acquaintance: Perception, Consciousness, and Empathy, Boston and Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See the Introduction to D. W. Smith, The Circle of Acquaintance.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Many of the issues here discussed come together in the logic, ontology, and phenomenology of self-awareness. See two complementary recent studies: D. W. Smith, The Circle of Acquaintance, and D. Zahavi, Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1999. Where the former analyzes the formal structure of self-awareness (and other types of acquaintance, or “intuition”), the latter analyzes the material structures of the same intentional phenomena.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Smith, D.W. (2002). What is “Logical” in Husserl’s Logical Investigations? The Copenhagen Interpretation. In: Zahavi, D., Stjernfelt, F. (eds) One Hundred Years of Phenomenology. Phaenomenologica, vol 164. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0093-1_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0093-1_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-6056-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-0093-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics