Skip to main content

Human Nature and Destiny

  • Chapter
Book cover The Thomist Tradition

Part of the book series: Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion ((HCPR,volume 2))

  • 257 Accesses

Abstract

According to the Aristotelian canons of definition to which Aquinas subscribed, a complete definition of something necessarily involves an articulation of its final cause. The final cause of a being is its end or telos in the sense of what it would be if it were to become fully realized, perfected, or completed according to its kind or nature. Understood as such, the final cause of a being is essentially connected to its formal cause because it expresses what it would mean for the form to realize its capacity for development into a perfected instance of its kind. In the light of this logic, it can be easily seen why the question of human nature is inextricably connected to the question of human destiny: it is impossible to understand what human nature is without knowing what it it is meant to become when fully realized. And since Aquinas’s overarching perspective is explicitly theocentric and theological, this means that considerations of human nature and human destiny must be set within the context of creation. In this light, what human nature is can only be understood in the light of what God the Creator intends as its end.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. ST I, 93, 4. On the doctrine of imago dei in Aquinas, a magisterial overview with good bibliographical references can be found in Jean Pierre Torrell, O.P., Saint Thomas d’Aquin, maître spirituel (Fribourg, Switzerland: Editions Universitaires de Fribourg, 1996), 105–132.

    Google Scholar 

  2. An overview of this debate can be found in Stephen J. Duffy, The Graced Horizon: Nature and Grace in Modern Catholic Thought (Collegeville, MN: The Liturgical Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See the overview in the first chapter, pp. 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Another development worthy of note in Thomistic anthropology is the dynamic and relational metaphysics of the person articulated by W. Norris Clarke in Person and Being (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  5. At the Origins of the Thomistic Notion of Man (New York: The MacMillan Company, 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Bernardo C. Bazan, “La coporalité selon saint Thomas,” La revue philosophique de Louvain 81 (1983): 369–409.

    Google Scholar 

  7. STI,76,5.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Aquinas sometimes refers to the soul as an intellectual substance, but he is careful also to point out that the human soul does not meet all the requirements for being a substance and can only be designated as such in a qualified sense. See Bazan’s “La corporalité selon Saint Thomas.” He has made this same point more recently in “The Human Soul: Form and Substance? Thomas Aquinas’ Critique of Eclectic Aristotelianism,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age 64 (1997): 95–126. See also Michael Sweeney, “Soul as Substance and Method in Aquinas’s Anthropological Writings,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du Moyen Age 66 (1999): 143–187.

    Google Scholar 

  9. SC 2, ad 16. See also ST I, 75, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  10. STI,75,2ad2.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For an interesting account of how Aquinas’s views show the inadequacy of the contemporary dichotomy of dualism against materialism, see Eleonore Stump, “Non-Cartesian Dualism and

    Google Scholar 

  12. Materialism without Reductionism,” Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 505–531. For a more ambitious attempt in this vein, see David Braine, The Human Person: Animal and Spirit (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1992), especially 480–531.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Two helpful accounts of Aquinas’s position are Herbert McCabe, “The Immortality of the Soul,” in Aquinas: A Collection of Critical Essays, ed. Anthony Kenny (Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor, 1969), 297–306 and Kenneth L. Schmitz “Purity of Soul and Immortality,” The Monist 69 (1986): 396–415. A useful classification of Aquinas’s arguments with some critical commentary can be found in David Ruel Foster, “Aquinas on the Immateriality of the Intellect,” The Thomist 55 (1991): 415–438. Negative verdicts on Aquinas’s reasoning can be found in Joseph A. Novak, “Aquinas on the Incorruptibility of the Soul,” The History of Philosophy Quarterly 4 (1987): 405–42 and Robert Pasnau, “Aquinas and the Content Fallacy,” The Modern Schoolman 76 (1998): 293–314.

    Google Scholar 

  14. STI,75,2.

    Google Scholar 

  15. ST I, 75, 6. For a penetrating commentary on the key point in this text, see Joseph Owens, “Aquinas on the Inseparability of Soul from Existence,” New Scholasticism 61 (1987): 249–270.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Aquinas derives the claim that each individual soul is directly created by God from the claim that the soul is immaterial and subsisting. No material power can produce an immaterial soul. See ST I, 118, 2. This topic is discussed more fully on pp. 86–88.

    Google Scholar 

  17. ST I, 84, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Anton Pegis, “The Separated Soul and its Nature in St. Thomas,” in St. Thomas Aquinas. 1274–1974. Commemorative Studies. Volume I., ed. Armand Maurer et alia (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1974), 130–158.

    Google Scholar 

  19. STI,89,1.

    Google Scholar 

  20. STI,89,2.

    Google Scholar 

  21. ST I, 89, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  22. “Elements of a Thomistic Philosophy of Death,” The Thomist 43 (1979): 587.

    Google Scholar 

  23. SCG IV, 79. See Anton Pegis, “Between Immortality and Death: Some Further Reflections on the Summa Contra Gentiles,” The Monist 58 (1974): 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  24. DA 1 ad 2. See also 2 ad 5 and 3. Joseph Owens has argued that Aquinas thinks that esse is the ultimate cause of the individuation of all beings, not just human souls, in his “Thomas Aquinas” in Individuation in Scholasticism: The Later Middle Ages and the Counter-Reformation (1150–1650), ed. Jorge Garcia (Albany: SUNY Press, 1994), 173–194.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Aquinas does think that the souls of the blessed will animate matter in a higher mode. See CT, 168.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Peter Geach endorses Aquinas’s doctrine of immortality without appreciating, however, the role played by esse in “Immortality,” God and the Soul (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969), 17–29.

    Google Scholar 

  27. SCG IV, 79.

    Google Scholar 

  28. “The Highest Encomium of Human Body,” in Littera, Sensus, Sententia, ed. A Lobato (Milan: Massimo, 1991), 99–116.

    Google Scholar 

  29. ST I-II, 4, 5 and 6.

    Google Scholar 

  30. The standard book on this topic is Jorge Laporta, La destinée de la nature humaine selon Thomas d’Aquin (Paris: J. Vrin, 1965). A short masterful analysis of the problem treated in this section is Etienne Gilson, “Sur la problématique de la vision béatifique,” Archives d’histoire doctrinales et litéraire du moyen âge 31 (1964): 67–88. See also Joseph Owens, C.S.S.R, Human Destiny (Washington, D. C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  31. See David Gallagher, “Thomas Aquinas on the Will as Rational Appetite,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 29 (1991): 559–584.

    Google Scholar 

  32. ST I-II, 3, 8.

    Google Scholar 

  33. ST I-II, 5, 8.

    Google Scholar 

  34. ST I, 62, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  35. STI,5,5.

    Google Scholar 

  36. ST I, 12, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  37. (Paris: Aubier, 1946). Perhaps the most perspicuous Thomistic philosophical response to DeLubac was Anton Pegis, “Nature and Spirit: Some Reflections on the Problem of the End of Man,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 23 (1949): 62–79.

    Google Scholar 

  38. STI,12,1.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See Pegis, “Nature and Spirit,” 73.

    Google Scholar 

  40. On this topic see Bernard Lonergan’s Grace and Freedom (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Gilson and LaPorta both make this point.

    Google Scholar 

  42. The problem of human finality has recently been the object of debate again because of the publication of Denis Bradley’s Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good: Reason and Human Happiness in Aquinas’s Moral Science (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1997). I discuss Bradley’s thesis, with which I am in sympathy, in Chapter Six. More traditional readings of Aquinas are offered by Stephen Long in “On the Possibility of a Purely Natural End for Man,” The Thomist 64 (2000): 211–237 and Peter A. Pagan-Aguiar, “St. Thomas Aquinas and Human Finality: Paradox or Mysterium Fidei?” The Thomist 64 (2000): 375–399.

    Google Scholar 

  43. “If any single topic offers the best access to Rahner’s immensely prolific and varied work, it is surely the nature/grace controversy.” Fergus Kerr, Immortal Longings (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1997), 179.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Theological Investigations, Vol. 1, trans. Cornelius Ernst (Baltimore: Helicon Press, 1961), 297–318.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Richard Reno describes Rahner’s position as formally extrinsicist because he distinguishes nature and grace but materially intrinsicist because of the tight fit between human longing and grace in The Ordinary Transformed: Karl Rahner and the Christian Vision of Transcendence (Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1995), 109–133.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., 299.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid., 302–3.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., 312.

    Google Scholar 

  49. This claim has obvious implications for an approach to non-Christian religions that will be explored in Chapter Eight.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid., 313.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See Nicholas H. Healy, “Indirect Methods in Theology: Karl Rahner as an Ad Hoc Apologist,” The Thomist 56 (1992): 613–630.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Rahner’s style of thinking, and Transcendental Thomism in general, is not at all congenial to Analytical Thomists.

    Google Scholar 

  53. See the overview in Chapter One, pp. 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Spirit in the World, trans. William Dych, S.J. (New York: Herder and Herder, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  55. The second revised edition was published in German in 1963 and translated into English as Hearers of the Word, trans. Michael Richards (New York: Herder & Herder, 1969). The revised edition bears such a strong imprint of Johannes Baptist Metz, a former student to whom Rahner entrusted the revisions, that it is not clear where Rahner leaves off and Metz begins. Because of Metz’s heavy hand, and because some Rahner scholars think that Richards’s translation is not entirely reliable, Joseph Donceel did a new translation of the first edition that has been published as Hearer of the Word, edited and with an introduction by Andrew Tallon (New York: Continuum, 1994). In what follows I shall be refering to this translation because I am persuaded by Donceel and Tallon that it is a more accurate reflection of Rahner’s thought.

    Google Scholar 

  56. “In Hearer of the Word we have the single most accessible and necessary book of philosophy and pretheology Rahner ever wrote.” Andrew Tallon, “Editor’s Introduction,” xix.

    Google Scholar 

  57. “Karl Rahner,” in The Modern Theologians, Second Edition, ed. David Ford (Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1997), 124.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Hearer of the Word, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ib1d.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., 26.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., 30.

    Google Scholar 

  62. “Erkennen ist Beisichsein des Seins, und dieses Beisichsein ist das Sein das Seinden” is the way Rahner puts it in Spirit in the World, 69.

    Google Scholar 

  63. It should be noted that when Aquinas uses this kind of language to describe knowing, he is consciously adopting a Neoplatonic formulation from the Liber de causis to describe self-knowledge.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Hearer of the Word, 33.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Ibid., 46.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ibid., 47.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ibid., 47–48.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid., 51.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See Spirit in the World, 135–226 where Rahner interprets agent intellect as excessus ad esse.

    Google Scholar 

  70. A classic traditional Thomistic critique is James P. Reichmann, “The Transcendental Method and the Psychogenesis of Being,” The Thomist 32 (1968): 449–508. While Reichmann’s critique is directed more at Emil Coreth than at Rahner, nonetheless it articulates the basic traditional complaint against any form of Transcendental Thomism: it never gets out of the head to the real.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Hearer of the Word, 53.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ibid., 68.

    Google Scholar 

  73. See “On the Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology,” in Theological Investigations, Vol. 4, trans. Kevin Smyth (New York: Seabury Press, 1966), 36–73.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Hearer of the Word, 81.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid., 81.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Ibid., 82.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., 83.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ibid.. 88.

    Google Scholar 

  79. This is the complaint of Fergus Kerr in Theology After Wittgenstein (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986), 14: “there is surely a prima facie case for suggesting that Rahner’s most characteristic theological profundities are embedded in an extremely mentalist-individualist epistemology of unmistakably Cartesian provenance. Central to his whole theology, that is to say, is the possibility for the individual to occupy a standpoint beyond his immersion in the bodily, the historical and the institutional.”

    Google Scholar 

  80. Hearer of the Word, 103.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ibid., 110.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid., 142.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Ibid., 153.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Rahner’s own mature presentation of his transcendental theology is Foundations of Christian Faith, trans. William V. Dych, S.J. (New York: Seabury, 1978). Dych authored a short overview of Rahner’s theology in the Liturgical Press’s Outstanding Christian Thinkers series as Karl Rahner (Collegeville, MN: 1992). For more on Rahner’s anthropology, see Andrew Tallon, Personal Becoming. Karl Rahner’s Metaphysical Anthropology (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1982). A nice collection of Rahner’s writings is in A Rahner Reader, ed. Gerald A. McCool (New York: Seabury Press, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shanley, B.J. (2002). Human Nature and Destiny. In: The Thomist Tradition. Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, vol 2. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9916-0_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9916-0_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5849-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9916-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics