Skip to main content

Religion and Morality

  • Chapter
The Thomist Tradition

Part of the book series: Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion ((HCPR,volume 2))

  • 257 Accesses

Abstract

Thomas Aquinas never articulated a systematic account of a purely philosophical ethics. When writing in his own name, as opposed to commenting on Aristotle, Aquinas’s interest in ethical matters is always explicitly framed by his understanding of moral science as part of the larger project of theology as sacra doctrina. 1 In the course of articulating a moral theology, Aquinas makes systematic use of some basic Aristotelian philosophical categories and doctrines from the Nichomachean Ethics. Indeed, the explicitly moral section of the Summa theologiae, the Second Part, begins with a consideration of beatitude and is structured according to a treatment of the virtues. This heavy reliance on Aristotle, along with what appears to be a relative reticence to incorporate specifically Christian doctrines into the discussion, has led some to conclude that Thomistic moral theology is really just a lightly baptized version of Aristotelian ethics. Yet as Servais Pinckaers has shown, Aquinas’s moral thought is fundamentally evangelical when properly and holistically understood.2 At the heart of Aquinas’s vision is not Aristotelian eudaimonia, but rather the Beatitudes of the Gospels; the primary resource for moral action is not acquired Aristotelian virtue, but the grace of the Holy Spirit poured out into the hearts of believers through the death and resurrection of Jesus Christ; the primary law is not some version of Stoic natural law, but rather the new law of the gospel.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See the account of sacra doctrina in Chapter Two.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Servais Pinckaers, O.P., trans. Sr. Mary Thomas Noble, O.P., The Sources of Christian Ethics (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1995), see especially 168–190. Pinckaers is the pre-eminent contemporary interpreter of Aquinas’s moral thought.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The attempt to focus on natural law as the primary category for Thomistic ethics appears to be at odds with Aquinas’s preference for a virtue-centered ethic. The relationship between natural law and virtue has been a point of dispute among Thomists, but in this context we must leave that debate aside. Pinckaers’s account of how natural law and virtue functions within Aquinas’s moral theology is surely correct.

    Google Scholar 

  4. “La béatitude dans l’éthique de Saint Thomas” in The Ethics of Thomas Aquinas, ed. L.J. Elders and K. Hedwig, Studii Tomistici 25 (Vatican: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1984), 80–94. See also the earlier reference to Sources of Christian Ethics.

    Google Scholar 

  5. “La béatitude dans l’éthique de Saint Thomas,” 89. The translation is mine.

    Google Scholar 

  6. STI-II,3,8.

    Google Scholar 

  7. ST I, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The best study of the question is Jorge Laporta, La destinée de la nature humaine selon Thomas d’Aquin, Études de philosophie médiévale, 55 (Paris: J. Vrin, 1965). A fuller discussion of the relationship between human nature and the beatific vision is central to the next chapter on Human Nature and Destiny.

    Google Scholar 

  9. ST I-II, 62, 1. The reference is to the same doctrine in the earlier 5, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  10. ST I-II, 3, 5. This would make Aquinas a “dominant end” interpreter of Aristotle.

    Google Scholar 

  11. IV Sent. d.49, g.1, a. l, sol 4.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Volume III in his Opera omnia, ed. Victorino Rodriguez, O.P. (Madrid: Consejo Suerior de Investigaciones Cientificas, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Revised edition (Paris: J. Aubier, 1942).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., II.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See Chapter Two, pp. 37–38.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Originally published in 1963, it has recently been reprinted in a revised third edition (Hamburg: Felix Meiner, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  17. See his Ethica Thomistica: The Moral Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, revised edition (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1997) and Aquinas on Human Action: A Theory of Practice (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid. Mclnerny’s remarks on the continuity between Aristotle and Aquinas are a reaction against the views of René Antoine Gauthier, who argued that Aquinas’s theological perspective led him to alter Aristotle’s ethics in significant ways. See Mclnerny’s discussion in Aquinas on Human Action, 169–185. I think Gauthier is right.

    Google Scholar 

  19. The Question of Christian Ethics, 38.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See the discussion of this in Chapter Two, pp. 37–43.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The Question of Christian Ethics, 59.

    Google Scholar 

  22. “The Role of God in the Philosophical Ethics of Thomas Aquinas,” in Miscellanea Mediaevalia V. 26: Was ist Philosophie im Mittelalter?, ed. Jan A. Aertsen and Andreas Speer (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1998), 1024–1033.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., 1025.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., 1027.

    Google Scholar 

  25. ST II-II, 85, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  26. ST I, 60, 5 and I-II, 109, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  27. G. Stevens, “The Disinterested Love of God according to St. Thomas and some of his Modern Interpreters,” The Thomist (1953): 307–333; 497–541.

    Google Scholar 

  28. SCG I, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  29. ST I-II, 109, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  30. I argue this at greater length in “Aquinas on Pagan Virtue,” The Thomist 63 (1999): 553–557.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Science and Wisdom, trans. Bernard Wall (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1936).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., 164. Emphasis in original.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., viii.

    Google Scholar 

  34. “Sur l’organization du savior morale,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 23 (1934): 258–280, and “Questions disputées de science morale,” Revue des sciences philosophiques et théologiques 28 (1937): 278–306.

    Google Scholar 

  35. “Sur l’organisation du savior morale,” Bulletin Thomiste (1935): 424–432 and “De Philosophia Morali Christiana,” Divus Thomas (Fribourg) 14 (1936): 87–122; 181–204.

    Google Scholar 

  36. (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., xi.

    Google Scholar 

  38. This would be an example of Christian philosophy insofar as reason establishes on its own grounds a truth which it only came to recognize on the basis of faith. See the discussion of Christian philosophy in Chapter Two, pp. 40–43.

    Google Scholar 

  39. In this context, see especially Pegis’s response to Henri DeLubac in “Nature and Spirit: Some Reflections on the Problem of the End of Man,” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 23 (1949): 62–79. A fuller discussions of Thomistic anthropology can be found in Chapter Seven.

    Google Scholar 

  40. ST I, 12, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  41. (Paris: J Aubier, 1946).

    Google Scholar 

  42. See Chapter Seven.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Bk I, c. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  44. The complex functioning of law within Aquinas’s moral theology cannot be discussed here. It is worth stressing again, however, that the entire discussion of law is explicitly theological because it culminates in the new law of grace: “[Aquinas] distinguishes five kinds of law: the eternal law, divine source of all legislation; the natural law, that is its direct participation in the human heart; and then the human law that is derived from the natural law. Revelation adds to this the Old Law, concentrated in the

    Google Scholar 

  45. Decalogue, which rejoins the natural law; and the evangelical Law of the New Testament. These different laws are connected by a true dynamism that originates in the eternal law, descends through the natural law to civil law, and then returns towards God its summit in the evangelical law, which is the most perfect participation here below in the eternal law, and the closest approach to the ultimate end proposed to us.” Pinckaers, Sources of Christian Ethics, 181. I have modified the translation.

    Google Scholar 

  46. ST I-II, 90, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See ST I-II, 91, 1 and 93, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  48. 47STI-II,91,2.

    Google Scholar 

  49. ST I-II, 100, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  50. ST I-II, 100, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  51. ST I-II, 100, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  52. ST I-II, 100, 3 ad 1.

    Google Scholar 

  53. ST I-II, 100, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  54. ST I-II, 99, 2 ad 2.

    Google Scholar 

  55. ST I-II, 95, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  56. ST I, 1 2

    Google Scholar 

  57. DT1,3ad4.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Grisez’s major focus has been on systematic moral theology in The Way of the Lord Jesus, 3 vol. (Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press, 1983, 1993, 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  59. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., 34.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., 48–9.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ibid., 94.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid., 89–90.

    Google Scholar 

  64. See the “Preface,” vi-vii.

    Google Scholar 

  65. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ibid., viii.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ibid.. 85–86.

    Google Scholar 

  68. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).

    Google Scholar 

  69. Ibid., 116–138.

    Google Scholar 

  70. (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  71. “What is the End of the Human Person? The Vision of God and Integral Human Fulfillment,” in Moral Truth and Moral Tradition, ed. Luke Gormally (London: Four Courts Press, 1994), 68–96. .

    Google Scholar 

  72. Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), 188.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopedia, Geneology, and Tradition (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990), 135.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ibid., 141.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid., 137.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., 140.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, 181.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Three Rival Versions, 140.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  81. See the reviews of Whose Justice? Which Rationality? by Thomas Nagel, “Maclntyre Versus the Enlightenment,” in Other Minds: Critical Essays 1969–1994 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), 203–209 and by Martha Nussbaum, “Recoiling from Reason,” New York Review of Books 36, n. 19 (December 7, 1989), 36–41.

    Google Scholar 

  82. For example, I argue that Maclntyre is too pessimistic about human nature and the possibility of virtue in my “Pagan Virtue.” Robert George has argued that Maclntyre’s account of natural law is too relativistic in “Moral Particularism, Thomism, and Traditions,” Review of Metaphysics 42 (1989): 593–605.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Three Rival Versions, 146.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Ibid., 147.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2002 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shanley, B.J. (2002). Religion and Morality. In: The Thomist Tradition. Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, vol 2. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9916-0_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9916-0_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5849-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9916-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics