Advertisement

Mathematics, Representation and Molecular Structure

  • Robin Findlay Hendry
Chapter
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science book series (BSPS, volume 222)

Abstract

The application of quantum-theoretic models to the explanation of chemical structure and bonding is one of the great twentieth-century stories of interaction among disciplines. Some philosophers have found in this interaction both evidential support and historical explanation. The evidential support is for the philosophical doctrine of physicalism, the thesis that everything is, or depends in some way on, the physical. The historical explanation concerns the fall of emergentism, and in particular its doctrines concerning the independence of chemical law. With the emergence of quantum chemistry, the physicalists argue, chemical structure and bonding was explained in terms of physical laws, and the hitherto popular and plausible philosophical view that chemical laws were in some sense sui generis was rendered less popular and plausible, at least among scientifically oriented philosophers.

Keywords

Quantum Chemistry Semantic View Downward Causation Empirical Adequacy Epistemic Virtue 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Broad, C. D. The Mind and Its Place in Nature. London: Kegan Paul, Trench and Trubner, 1925.Google Scholar
  2. Bueno, O. “What is Structural Empiricism? Scientific Change in an Empiricist Setting.” Erkenntnis 50 (1999): 59–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Cartwright, N. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cartwright, N., T. Shomar, and M. Suarez. “The Tool Box of Science.” in Theories and Models in Scientific Processes, Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 44, edited by W. E. Herfel, W. Krajewski, I. Niiniluoto and R. Wójcicki, 137–49. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi, 1995.Google Scholar
  5. Coulson, C. A. Valence. 2d ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961.Google Scholar
  6. Demopoulos, W., and M. Friedman. “The Concept of Structure in the Analysis of Matter.” in Rereading Russell, edited by C. Wade Savage and C. Anthony Anderson, 183–99. Vol. 12, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989.Google Scholar
  7. Downes, S. “The importance of Models in Theorizing: A Deflationary Semantic View.” In Psa 1992, edited by D. Hull, M. Forbes and K. Okruhlik, 142–53. Vol. 1. East Lansing MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 1992.Google Scholar
  8. Fraassen, B. C. van. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Fraassen, B. C. “Structure and Perspective: Philosophical Perplexity and Paradox.” in Logic and Scientific Methods, edited by M. Dalla Chiara et al., 511–30. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1997.Google Scholar
  10. Fraassen, B. C. van, and J. Sigman. “interpretation in Science and the Arts.” In Realism and Representation: Essays on the Problem of Realism in Relation to Science, Literature and Culture, edited by G. Levine, 73–99. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1993.Google Scholar
  11. Francoeur, E. “The Forgotten Tool: The Design and Use of Molecular Models.” Social Studies of Science 27 (1997): 7–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. French, S., and J. Ladyman. “Semantic Perspective on Idealisation in Quantum Mechanics.” In Idealisation in Contemporary Physics, Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 63, edited by N. Shanks, 51–73. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1998.Google Scholar
  13. French, S., and J. Ladyman. “Reinflating the Semantic Approach.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (1999): 103–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Giere, R. N. Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988. . “Visual Models and Scientific Judgment.” In Picturing Knowledge: Historical and Philosophical Problems Concerning the Use of Art in Science,edited by B. S. Baigrie, 269–302.Google Scholar
  15. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996.Google Scholar
  16. Goodman, N. Languages of Art. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1968.Google Scholar
  17. Hankins, T. L. “Blood, Dirt and Nomograms.” History of Science 90 (1999): 50–80.Google Scholar
  18. Hendry, R. F. “Models and Approximations in Quantum Chemistry.” In Idealization in Contemporary Physics, Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 63, edited by N. Shanks, 123–42. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Rodopi, 1998.Google Scholar
  19. Hendry, R. F. “Molecular Models and the Question of Physicalism.” Hyle 5 (1999): 117–34.Google Scholar
  20. Hendry, R. F. “Chemistry and the Completeness of Physics.” In Proceedings of the 11th International Congress of Logic. Methodology and Philosophy of Science, edited by J. Cachro, S. Hanuszewicz, G. Kurczewski and A. Rojszczak. Dordrecht: Kluwer, forthcoming in 2001.Google Scholar
  21. Hendry, R. F., and S. Psillos. “How to Do Things with Theories: An interactive View of Language and Models in Science.” Unpublished manuscript, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  22. Horgan, T. “From Supervenience to Superdupervenience: Meeting the Demands of a Material World.” Mind 102 (1993): 555–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hughes, R. L G. “Models and Representation.” Philosophy of Science 64 (Proceedings) (1997): S325 - S336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Knight, D. M. “Scientific Theory and Visual Language.” In The Natural Sciences and the Arts: Aspects of Interaction from the Renaissance to the 20th Century, edited by A. Ellenius, 106–24. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell international, 1985, reprinted in D. M. Knight, Science in the Romantic Era ( Aldershot: Ashgate, 1998 ), 177–95.Google Scholar
  25. Knight, D. M. “Illustrating Chemistry.” In Picturing Knowledge: Historical and Philosophical Problems Concerning the Use of Art in Science, edited by B. S. Baigrie, 135–63. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996.Google Scholar
  26. McLaughlin, B. “The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism.” In Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects for Non-Reductive Physicalism, edited by A. Beckermann, H. Flohr and J. Kim, 49–93. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1992.Google Scholar
  27. Meinel, C. “Modelling a Visual Language for Chemistry, 1860–1875.” Paper presented at the Conference: Types of Paper Tools and Traditions of Representations in the History of Chemistry, MPIWG Berlin 1999.Google Scholar
  28. Morrison, M. “Modelling Nature: Between Physics and the Physical World.” Philosophia Naturalis 35 (1998): 65–85.Google Scholar
  29. Newman, M. H. A. “Mr. Russell’s `Causal Theory of Perception’.” Mind 37 (1928).Google Scholar
  30. Nye, Mary Jo. “Explanation and Convention in Nineteenth-Century Chemistry.” In New Trends in the History of Science, edited by R. Visser et al. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1989.Google Scholar
  31. Nye, Mary Jo. “Physics and Chemistry: Commensurate or Incommensurate Sciences?” In The Invention of Physical Science, edited by M. J. Nye, J. L. Richards and R. H. Stuewer. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992. From Chemical Philosophy to Theoretical Chemistry. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993.Google Scholar
  32. Pang, Alex Soojung-Kim. “Visual Representation and Post-Constructivist History of Science.” Hist. Stud. Phys. Biol. Sci. 28 (1997): 139–72.Google Scholar
  33. Papineau, David. Philosophical Naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell, 1993.Google Scholar
  34. Papineau, David. “The Rise of Physicalism.” In The Proper Ambition of Science, edited by M. W. F. Stone and Jonathan Wolff. London: Routledge, 2000.Google Scholar
  35. Park, Buhm Soon. “Chemical Translators: Pauling, Wheland and Their Strategies for Teaching Theory of Resonance.” British Journal for the History of Science 32 (1999): 21–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Park, Buhm Soon. “Graphs, Pictures and Diagrams: Visual Representations in the Making of QuantumGoogle Scholar
  37. Park, Graphs, Pictures and Diagrams: Visual Representaions in the Making of Quantum Chemistry. Paper presented at the Conference: Types of Paper Tools and Traditions of Representations in the History of Chemistry, MPIWG Berlin 1999.Google Scholar
  38. Psillos, S. Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge, 1999.Google Scholar
  39. Rheinberger, Hans-Jörg. Toward a History of Epistemic Things: Synthesizing Proteins in the Test Tube. Stanford: Standford University Press, 1997.Google Scholar
  40. Ritter, C. “Rhetoric and Logics of Participation in the Visual Practice of Nineteenth-Century Chemistry: The Development of Crum Brown’s Graphical Formulas as Paper Tools.” Paper presented at the Conference: Types of Paper Tools and Traditions of Representations in the History of Chemistry, MPIWG Berlin 1999.Google Scholar
  41. Rocke, Alan J. Chemical Atomism in the Nineteenth Century: From Dalton to Cannizzaro. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
  42. Rudwick, M. J. “The Emergence of a Visual Language for Geological Science 1760–1840.” History of Science 14 (1976): 149–95.Google Scholar
  43. Servos, J. W. Physical Chemistry from Ostwald to Pauling. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990. Simoes, A., and K. Gavroglu. “Quantum Chemistry qua Applied Mathematics: The Contributions of Charles Alfred Coulson.” Hist. Stud. Phys. Btol. Sci. 29 (1999): 363–406.Google Scholar
  44. Suarez, M. “Theories, Models and Representations.” In Model-Based Reasoning in Scientific Discovery, edited by L. Magnani et al. New York: Plenum, 2000.Google Scholar
  45. Suppe, F. “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories.” In The Structure of Scientific Theories, edited by F. Suppe. 2d ed. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1977.Google Scholar
  46. Suppe, F The Semantic Conception of Theories and Scientific Realism. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1989.Google Scholar
  47. Trumpler, M. “From Tabletops to Triangles: Increasing Abstraction in the Depiction of Experiments in Animal Electricity from Galvani to Ritter.” In Luigi Galvani International Workshop Proceedings, Bologna Studies in the History of Science 7, edited by M. Bresadola and G. Pancaldi, 115–45. Bologna: Università di Bologna, 1999.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2001

Authors and Affiliations

  • Robin Findlay Hendry
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of DurhamUK

Personalised recommendations