Skip to main content

Spirit, Chemical Principles and Atoms in France in the First Half of the Seventeenth Century

  • Chapter
Elements, Principles and Corpuscles

Abstract

In France, as distinct from Germany, Paracelsianism and chemistry were up against a strong and enduring opposition, on both intellectual and political grounds.1 The medical establishment launched a virulent attack on Paracelsian medicine — witness the antimony controversy. In the second half of the sixteenth century, Paracelsianism was becoming widespread among Paris physicians and, as Didier Kahn has shown, Roch le Baillif was by no means alone.2 The supposed association of alchemists and Paracelsians with the Rosicrucians contributed towards dramatising the controversies over Paracelsianism. 3

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. For a general view of Paracelsianism, see A.G. Debus, The Chemical Philosophy, 2 vols, (New York, 1977)

    Google Scholar 

  2. W. Pagel, The Smiling Spleen. Paracelsianism in Storm and Stress (Basle, 1984)

    Google Scholar 

  3. H. Trevor Roper, ‘The Paracelsian Movement’, in Renaissance Essays (London, 1986), pp. 149–99

    Google Scholar 

  4. J. Telle (ed.), Parega Paracelsica. Paracelsus in Vergangenheit und Gegenwart (Stuttgart, 1991); id. (ed.), Analecta Paracelsica. Studien zum Nachleben Theophrast von Hohenheims im deutschen Kulturgebiet der frühen Neuzeit (Stuttgart, 1994); H. Schott und I. Zinguer (eds.), Paracelsus und seine internationale Rezeption in der frühen Neuzeit. Beiträge zur Geschichte des Paracelsismus (Leiden, 1998); O.P. Grell (ed.), Paracelsus: the Man and his Reputation, his Ideas and their Transformation (Leiden, 1998). For the French scene, see Metzger, Doctrines Chimiques; H. Guerlac, ‘Guy de La Brosse and the French Paracelsians’, in A.G. Debus (ed.), Science, Medicine and Society in the Renaissance. Essays to Honor Walter Pagel 2 vols. (New York, 1972), i, pp. 177–85; H. Trevor-Roper, ‘The Sieur de la Rivière’, in Renaissance Essays, pp. 200–22; A.G. Debus, The French Paracelsians. The Chemical Challenge to Medical and Scientific Tradition in Early Modern France (Cambridge, 1991); and Didier Kahn, ‘Paracelsisme et alchimie en France à la fin de la Renaissance (1567–1625)’ (unpublished dissertation, Paris IV, 1998).

    Google Scholar 

  5. D. Kahn, ‘La Faculté de Médecine de Paris en échec face au Paracelsisme: enjeux et dénouement réels du procès de Roch le Baillif, in Schott and Zinguer (n. 1), pp. 146–221.

    Google Scholar 

  6. On the ‘antimony war’, see P. Pilpoul, La querelle de Vantimoine (Paris, 1928) and A.G. Debus, French Paracelsians (n. 1), pp. 21–30.

    Google Scholar 

  7. On Renaudot see H.M. Solomon, Public Welfare, Science and Propaganda in Seventeenth-Century France: The Innovations of Théophraste Renaudot (Princeton, 1972). On Guy de la Brosse see DSB, Guerlac (n. 1); and id., ‘Guy de la Brosse: Botanist, Chemist, and Libertine’, in H. Guerlac, Essays and Papers in the history of Modern Science (Baltimore and London, 1977), pp. 440–50; R.C. Howard, ‘Guy de La Brosse and the Jardin des Plantes’, in H. Woolf (ed.), The Analytic Spirit. Essays in the History of Science in Honor of Henry Guerlac (Ithaca and London, 1981), pp. 195–224; id., La bibliothèque et le laboratoire de Guy de la Brosse au Jardin des Plantes à Paris (Geneva, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Following Petrus Severinus, de la Brosse conceived water and earth as matrices and receptacles of the semina rerum. See G. de La Brosse, De la Nature, Vertu et Utilité des Plantes (Paris, 1628), pp. 289–440.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Metzger, Doctrines Chimiques, p. 233; R. Lenoble, Mersenne ou la naissance du mécanisme, (Paris, 1943) pp. 134–153 and Debus (n. 1), pp. 154–155.

    Google Scholar 

  10. W. Harvey, Exercitationes duae Anatomicae de Circulatione Sanguinis ad Joannem Riolanum filium (Rotterdam, 1648), pp. 66–7.

    Google Scholar 

  11. J. d’Espagnet, Enchiridion Physicae Restitutae (Paris, 1608). References are taken from the 1642 Paris edition, pp. 131, 137, 147–8. On Jean d’Espagnet (1564–1637), see Ferguson, Bibliotheca Chemica; F. Secret, “Littérature et alchimie, X: Mlle de Gournay alchimiste”, Bibliothèque d’Humanisme et Renaissance, 35 (1973), 526–531; T. Willard, ‘The Many Worlds of Jean d’Espagnet’, in A.G. Debus and M.T. Walton (eds), Reading the Book of Nature. The Other Side of the Scientific Revolution (Kirksville, Missouri, 1998), pp. 201–14.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. B.J.T. Dobbs, The Foundations of Newton’s Alchemy, or The Hunting of the Greene Lyon (Cambridge, 1984), pp. 37–9, 153. A source of d’Espagnet’s view of universal spirit and magnets might be M. Sendivogius’s Novum Lumen Chymicum (Prague, 1604). On Sendivogius, see DSB. As we shall see in chapter 4, the quest for the celestial magnet crops up in Boyle’s Correspondence of 1659.

    Google Scholar 

  13. D’Espagnet(n. 8), p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. Lasswitz, Geschichte, i, pp. 333–9. d’Espagnet’s atomism is ignored by Dobbs and by Debus. The latter labelled d’Espagnet’s Enchiridion a “mystical writ”, French Paracelsians, (n. 1), p. 177.

    Google Scholar 

  15. D’Espagnet (n. 8), pp. 122–4.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., pp. 44–5; 119–20.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Nuysement, Traittez de l’Harmonie et Constitution generalle du vray sel, secret des Philosophes, & de l’Esprit universel du Mond (Paris 1621), pp. 2; 11; 17; 23. On Nuysement see W. Kirsop, ‘Clovis Hesteau, sieur de Nuysement, et la littérature alchimique en France à la fin du XVIe et au début du XVIIe siècle’ (unpublished dissertation, Université de Paris, 1960). As S. Matton (‘La figure de Démogorgon dans la littérature alchimique’, in D. Kahn and S. Matton, Alchimie: art, histoire et mythes (Paris and Milan, 1995), pp. 308–17), and D. Kahn (n. 2) have demonstrated, Nuysement’s Traittez is entirely based on Jean Brouaut’s Trois livres des elemens chymiques et spagyriques.

    Google Scholar 

  18. H. de Rochas, La Physique Reformée, contenant la refutation des erreurs populaires, et le triomphe des veritez philosophiques... (Paris, 1648, first edn: 1638), pp. 60, 133; id., La Physique demonstrative, (Paris, 1644), pp. 148–9; id., Histoire des eaux mineralles (Paris, 1648), 2 parts with separate pagination, part i, pp. 31, 234, 239–51. On Rochas (1619–1648) see Ferguson, Bibliotheca Chemica and S. Matton, “Henry de Rochas plagiaire des ‘Trois livres des elemens chymiques et spagyriques’ de Jean Brouaut”, Chrysopoeia 5 (1992–1996), 703–719.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Rochas, La Physique (n. 15), p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Rochas, Histoire des eaux mineralles (n. 15), vol. i, pp. 174–6 and vol. ii (separate pagination), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  21. S. Basso, Philosophiae Naturalis adversus Aristotelem libri XII (Amsterdam, 1649, first edn Geneva 1621). On Sebastien Basso’s life, see DBI and C. Lüthy, Thoughts and Circumstances of Sébastien Basson. Analysis, Micro-history, Questions’, Early Science and Medicine 111 (1997), 1–73. On Basso’s philosophy, see Lasswitz, Geschichte, i, pp. pp.467–81; T. Gregory, ‘Studi sull’Atomismo del Seicento, I’, Giornale Critico della Filosofia Italiana 44 (1964), 38–65; G. Zanier, ‘II macrocosmo corpuscolaristico di Sebastiano Basson’, in Ricerche sull’Atomismo del Seicento (Firenze, 1977), pp. 77–118, L.O. Nielsen, ‘A Seventeenth-Century Physician on God and Atoms: Sebastian Basso’, N. Kretzmann (ed.), Meaning and Inference in Medieval Philosophy (Dordrecht, 1988), pp. 297–369.

    Google Scholar 

  22. “Caeterum quomodo ex illis diversissimis particulis primis partes in infinitum discrepantes conflari possint; atque per aliquarum particularum, vel detractionem, vel additionem, vel situs partium variationem, aliae in aliarum naturam facile transeant, non intellectu est difficile.”, Basso (n. 18), pp. 72; 118 and 387.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 302. Nielsen stresses that the motion of ether, and consequently of atoms, completely depend on God’s will. See Nielsen (n. 18), pp. 318–23 and 343–4.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Basso (n. 18), p. 391: “Diximus spiritum ilium universalem elementis coniunctum duplicem illis appetitum impertiri, similis scilicet coniunctionem, et spacium, locumque suae naturae debitum. Primus ille appetitus duos motus excitat, unum primarium quo scilicet simile attrahit simile, vel forte potius ad simile se recepit; neque enim vi fit talis attractio, sed amore. Alterum secundarium quo scilicet dum simile appetit similis connexionem”

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  26. “Vix ulla res est ex qua non eliciant tres naturas valde inter se differentes; quarum quae subtilior est et volatilior, spiritum vocant, seu etiam mercurium, Quae vero crassior et pinguior, oleum et sulphur appellant, Quae vero omnium maxime fixa ex intimis veluti partis cuiusque penetralibus ultima educitur, sal illis nuncupatur. Praeter has tres naturas valde utiles, superest quaedam materia terrestris et inutilis quam foeces vocant et caput mortuum, est insuper aquaeus quidam et insipidus liquor quae phlegma dicunt.” Ibid., pp. 31–2.

    Google Scholar 

  27. “Materia rerum ex minutissimis particulis diversae naturae comparata est; quae quidem naturae sive sint quatuor elementa: ignis, aër, aqua, terra; sive quid aliud prius, ex quo haec elementa componantur, speciei diversissimae sunt. Caeterum, naturas illas, quae ad ignem conficiendum sunt magis idoneae, nos ignem vocamus, & ita de caeteris.” Ibid., p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., p. 70. Cf. H.H. Kubbinga, ‘Les premières théories ‘moleculaire’: Isaac Beeckman (1620) et Sébastien Basson (1621). Le concept d’individu substantiel et d’espèce substantielle’, Revue d’Histoire des sciences 37 (1984), 215–33.

    Google Scholar 

  30. “Hae primae particulae adeo minutae sunt, ut nisi plurimae in unam molem coeëant, sensum non affîciant. [...] Hinc licet primae sint immutabiles quantum ad essentiam, secundae & tertiae & reliquae facile possunt aliae in aliarum naturam transire, paucioribus, aut pluribus mutatis, prout magis vel minus aliae ab aliis recedunt.” Basso (n. 18), p. 113.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid, p. 304. Cf. Zanier (n. 18), pp. 104–110.

    Google Scholar 

  32. According to Basso, air contains “varia rerum semina”, Basso (n. 18), p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Metzger, Doctrines chimiques, pp. 53–4. On Beguin, see T.S. Patterson, ‘Jean Beguin and his Tyrocinium Chymicum’, Annals of Science 2 (1937), 243–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. J-B. Morin, Refutation des theses erronees d’Antoine Villon…, & Etienne de Claves...(Paris, 1624). Mersenne, Verité des Sciences, (Paris, 1625), pp. 79–83. See D. Kahn, ‘Entre atomisme, alchimie et théologie: la réception des thèses d’Antoine de Villon et Étienne de Clave contre Aristote, Paracelse et les “cabalistes” (24–25 août 1624)’, Annals of Science, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Morin(n.31), pp. 13–7.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  37. E. de Clave, Paradoxes ou traittez philosophiques des pierres et pierreries (Paris, 1635). It would seem that the author had already written a number of tracts on mineralogy, chemistry and medicine before 1635. See ‘Preface’ sig. Eiijr‒v.

    Google Scholar 

  38. “Nous disons donc que ce n’est pas le lieu qui donne la faculté generative à la semence, ouy bien l’esprit qui est contenuu en icelle, excité au prealable par l’agent externe...” E. de Clave, Paradoxes (n. 34) p. 346. See also ibid. pp. 366–7.

    Google Scholar 

  39. “Car cet esprit seminaire, comme nous dirons plus amplement cy-aprés, est la vraye semence qui ouvre les elemens plus compactes, pour donner entrée en iceux aux autres moin grossiers, & qui neantmoins n’y pourroient avoir aucun accés sans cét esprit, qui ouvre et mesle toutes les autres substances diverses & heterogenes, pour les rendre comme homogenes, et les unir sous une mesme forme.” Ibid., p. 368.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  41. “Nous disons donc qu’il y a cinq corps simples, que nous appelions elemens, non pas à cause qu’ils sont simples: autrement le Ciel & l’air seroient elemens, ains seulment par ce qu’ils composent tous les mixtes.” E. de Clave, Nouvelle lumiere philosophique des vrais principes et elemens de nature (Paris, 1641), p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  42. “Il faut donc sçavoir que les Chymistes veulent que ce [l’esprit] une substance corporelle, la plus subtile & penetrante du mixte, laquelle estant liberée des liens d’iceluy, ouvre, dissout, penetre ou pennée les corps mixtes, voire le plus compactes, pour ayder à la separation des diverses, voire plus pures parties du mixte.” Ibid., p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid., p. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., pp. 46–7; 55. On fermentation in seventeenth-century chemistry and medicine, see W. Pagel, Jan Baptista van Helmont Reformer of Science and Meleme (Cambridge, 1982), pp. 79–87.

    Google Scholar 

  45. E. de Clave, Nouvelle Lumiere (n. 38), pp. 40–1.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., p. 101. It is somewhat surprising to see that spirit is both the most active and the heaviest principle. It is apparent that de Clave identifies spirit with mercury.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid., p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  48. “De ce que dessus nous pouvons inferer que la chaleur & la froideur sont bient un mouvement, & de plus sont qualitez tactiles, la chaleur, dautant qu’elle congrege & assemble les choses homogenes & de mesme nature, & separe les heterogenes ou dissimilaires, & en outre est une qualité qui affecte nostre attouchement, en sorte qu’elle separe tant qu’elle peut, & suivant sa chaleur plus ou moins grande, les choses heterogenes, premierement les plus volatiles, & en suite celles qui le sont moins, & neantmoins elle ne laisse de causer un mouvement de parties reverbéré en soy, parce qu’elle se met avec reverberation & prompte alteration: mais la difference qu’il y a de la chaleur de nos elemens à celle qui se fait par la reflexion & repercussion de la lumiere & de la collision reïterée des corps compactes, consiste en ce que toutes ces choses eschauffent par le seul mouvement; & nos trois elemens chauds, huile, esprit, & sel, produisent le mesme effect, non seulement par le mouvement, mais encores par leur qualité de chaleur, qui leur est tellement inherente & fixe, qu’ils ne peuvent recevoir aucune qualité contraire...” Ibid., pp. 223–4.

    Google Scholar 

  49. On the Conimbricenses’ commentaries, see D. des Chene, Physiologia. Natural Philosophy in Late Aristotelian and Cartesian Thought (Ithaca and London, 1996), passim.

    Google Scholar 

  50. E. de Clave, Nouvelle Lumiere (n. 38), pp. 275–6.

    Google Scholar 

  51. On Mersenne see Lenoble, Mersenne (n. 6); and P. Dear, Mersenne and the Learning of the Schools, (Ithaca-New York, 1988). On Mersenne and alchemy see Debus, French Paracelsians (n. 1), pp. 72–3; and A. Beaulieu, ‘L’attitude nuancée de Mersenne envers la chymie’, in J.-C. Margolin and S. Matton (eds.), Alchimie et philosophie à la Renaissance (Paris, 1993), pp. 395–403.

    Google Scholar 

  52. M. Mersenne, Quaestiones Celeberrimae in Genesim (Paris, 1623), cols. 539; 565–6. Besides attacking Paracelsus and Fludd, Mersenne selected Khunrath as a champion of the impious alchemy and magic. In the Questions Théologiques, Physiques, Morales et Mathematiques (Paris, 1634), pp. 133–4, Mersenne published, with approbation, the Sorbonne’s Censure of Heinrich Khunrath’s Anphitheatrum Sapientiae (1609), which reads: “La Sacrée Faculté de la Theologie de Paris, à tous les Catholiques Puisque l’Apostre nous enjoint d’éprouver toutes choses, & de retenir ce qui est bon, ayant apperceu que depuis quelques mois les Catholiques ont un certain livre tres-pernicieux entre les mains, dans lequel il y a premierement quelques figures, & puis plusieurs explications de divers passages de la saincte Escriture disposees par sept degrez, & finalement quelques corollaires, & dont le titre est L’Amphiteatre Christianocabalistique Divinomagique... la sudite Faculté de Theologie yant leu exactement, & examiné le livre entier par quelques docteurs qu’elle a specialement deputez pour ce sujet, a jugé que les explications estant prises à la lettre, & tous les corollaires pris comme ils sont, avec le livre mesme, doivent estre condamnés, particulierement parce qu’estant remply d’ipietez, d’erreurs, & d’Heresies, & d’une perpetuelle profanation sacrilege des passages de la saincte Escriture, il abuse de plus saints mysteres de la Religion Catholique, & conduit les lecteurs aux arts deffendus & abominables, c’est pourquoy elle a jugé qu’un livre si contageieux ne peut pas estre leu, ny exposé en public sans perte de la Foy, de la Religion, & de la pieté.”, dated March l, 1625.

    Google Scholar 

  53. M. Mersenne, L’Impieté des Déistes (Paris, 1624), pp. 238–9; id., Quaestiones Celeberrimae (n. 49), col. 1838. In La Verité des Sciences (Paris, 1625), pp. 78–83, Mersenne’s target was the theses of 1624. On van Goorle, see below, pp. 184–5; on Nicholas Hill, see below, pp. 75–7. See Nathanael Carpenter, Philosophia Libera (London, 1621). On Carpenter see DNB and C.B. Schmitt, ‘Nathanael Carpenter’, in F. Ueberweg, Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, revised edn (gen. ed. R.W. Meyer), Die Philosophie des 17. Jahrhunderts, 3: England, ed. J-P. Schobinger (Basle, 1988), pp. 355–6 and 488.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Mersenne, Quaestiones Celeberrimae (n. 49), ‘Praefatio’ and col. 1483; id., La Verité des Sciences (n. 50), pp. 105–6.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Mersenne, Questions Inouyes, ou Récréation des Sçavans (Paris, 1634), p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  56. On Mersenne’s theory of knowledge see R.H. Popkin, The History of Skepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1979), pp. 129–40; and P. Dear (n. 48), pp. 23–79.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Mersenne, Questions Inouyes (n. 52), p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Mersenne, Verité des Sciences (n. 50), p. 56, and id., Questions Inouyes, (n. 52), p. 124.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Mersenne, Questions Théologiques (n. 49), pp. 24–6.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., pp. 11–5.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., pp. 109–11.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Mersenne, Harmonie Universelle (Paris, 1636), p. 203.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Lenoble, Mersenne (n. 6), p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  64. On Stanihurst, see Mersenne, Correspondance, i, 274. On Lefèvre, see ibid, pp. 324–5.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Mersenne, Correspondance, i, pp. 280–2.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Mersenne, Correspondance, i, pp. 282–3.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Jean Rey (c.1582 — c.1645) was born at Le Bugue in Dordogne, M.D. at Montpellier, practised at Le Bogue. He was connected with several correspondents of Mersenne: Jean Brun, Deschamps, apothecary and physician of Bergerac, and Pierre Trichet of Bordeaux. A biographical account of Rey and a bibliography of his Essays is to be found in D. McKie’s introduction to the reprint of the Essays, see The Essays of Jean Rey (London, 1951), pp. ix–xliv.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Rey, Essay xvi, The Essays, (n. 64), p. 97 and Essay xxvi, ibid., p. 139.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Essay xiii, ibid., pp. 77–8.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Essay xii, ibid., p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Essay xxvii, ibid., pp. 140–1.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Théodore Deschamps (c. 1588 — ?) corresponded with Mersenne from 1640 to 1645. He studied in Leiden and practised medicine in Bergerac. See Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, p. 537.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Mersenne, Correspondance, v, pp. 573–7.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, pp. 276–7. On Hero’s Pneumatica, see M. Boas, ‘Hero’s Pneumatica. A Study of its Transmission and Influence’, Isis 40 (1949), 38–48.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Letter of 31 July 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, p. 539.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Letter of December 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, x, p. 369: “Maintenant touchant les animaux, il est evident que leur vie consiste en la chaleur, et la chaleur au mouvement des atomes plus menus, qui se meuvent dans les espaces des autres.”

    Google Scholar 

  77. ‘Lettre du Sieur Brun qui a donné subject au present discours’, Rey, Essays (n. 64), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, pp. 275–82.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Villiers was physician at Sens. The role of salt as the main agent in nature had already been stressed by Joseph Duchesne, cf. N.E. Emerton, The Scientific Reinterpretation of Form (Ithaca and London, 1984), pp. 209–220. In a letter to Mersenne of 28 October 1640 Descartes expressed a critical view of Villiers’s theory of matter, see AT, iii, pp. 211.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Villiers to Mersenne, June 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, p. 426.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, pp. 470–1.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Villiers to Mersenne June 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, p. 427.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Mersenne, Correspondance, x, p. 105.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Descartes, Météores, discours troisiesme, A.T., vi, p. 249.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Descartes to Mersenne 30 July 1640. Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, pp. 518–9.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Lazare Meyssonnier (1602–72) studied medicine at Montpellier and became médecin du Roy in 1642. See Nouvelle Biographie Générale, ed. Hoefer, 46 vols, (Paris 1862–66), s.v.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Meyssonnier to Mersenne 31 May 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, ix, pp.358–9.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Villiers to Mersenne, end of October 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, x, p. 198. See Descartes, Météores, discours vi and vii, AT, vi, pp. 291–324. Cfr. E. Gilson, Etudes sur le rôle de la pensée médiévale dans la formation du système cartésien (Paris, 19672), pp. 102–37.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Villiers to Mersenne 9/10 December 1640, Mersenne, Correspondance, x, p. 309.

    Google Scholar 

  90. On Jacques Gaffarel see R. Pintard, Le Libertinage érudit dans la première moite du XVII e siècle (Geneva, 19832), pp. 187–90. In 1625 Gaffarel published Abdita divinae Cabala mysteria, containing attacks on Mersenne, who in turn responded by publishing a short booklet, bearing the title De Gaffarello Judicio (s.1., 1625). See Mersenne, Correspondance, i, pp. 303–6.

    Google Scholar 

  91. J-B. van Helmont to Mersenne, 26 September 1630, Mersenne, Correspondance, ii, pp 530–40. In this letter van Helmont rejected the Paracelsian doctrine of signatures, claiming that the spirit contained in the seed produces the form of plants. On the doctrine of signatures, see M.L. Bianchi, Signatura rerum. Segni, magia e conoscenza da Paracelso a Leibniz (Rome, 1987). On van Helmont’s De Magnetica Vulnerum Curatione, see Pagel, van Helmont (n. 41), pp. 8–11.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Lasswitz, Geschichte, i, pp. 343–351.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Newman, Gehennical Fire, pp. 110–4.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Van Helmont, Totestas Medicaminum’, §§ 37–8, Ortus, p. 479.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Van Helmont, ‘Terra’, § 14, Ortus, p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Van Helmont, ‘Gas Aquae’, § 10, Ortus, p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Lasswitz, Geschichte, i, pp. 345–6, Newman, Gehennical Fire, pp. 112–3.

    Google Scholar 

  98. “Nunquam autem in aqua fieri trium primorum separationem, multoque minus essentialem transmutationemullam.” (‘Elementa’, §§ 15–16, Ortus, p. 53.).

    Google Scholar 

  99. This explanation is suggested by Hooykaas, ‘Het Begrip’, p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  100. “Haec suppono, pro ut Astronomi suos excentricos, ut intelligendi imbecillitati nostrae, eatur obviam.” (‘Gas Aquae’, §§ 8–9, Ortus, p. 74.). “Quod autem quandoque elemento aquae sua tria tribuerim, id analogice locutum est.” (‘Tria Prima Chymicorum...’, § 54, Ortus, p. 407).

    Google Scholar 

  101. “Seminibus quidem concessum est, ex aqua, sua fingere concreta, suamque tragoediam per formarum defluxum ad interitum ludere.” (‘Gas Aquae’, § 44, Onus, p. 80).

    Google Scholar 

  102. “Seminalis enim concreti proprietas, quae in Gas persévérât, vi frigoris, & dierum maturitate moritur & in pristinam aquam Gas redit”. (‘Complexionum atque Mistionum Elementalium Figmentum’, §§ 29, Onus, p. 108). On van Helmont’s concept of gas see Pagel, van Helmont (n. 41), pp. 61–3 and G. Giglioni, Ter una storia del termine Gas da van Helmont a Lavoisier: costanza e variazione del significato’, Annali délia Facoltà di Lettere e Filosofia deW Université di Macerata 25–26 (1992–3), 431–68, esp. 439–40.

    Google Scholar 

  103. ’Aër’, § 11, Onus, pp. 63–4.

    Google Scholar 

  104. “Duo igitur, nee plura, sunt corporum, & causarum corporalium prima initia. Elementum aquae nimirum, sive initium ex quo: & fermentum, sive initium séminale, per quod, id est dispositivum, unde mox producitur semen, in materia.”(‘Causae et initia naturalium’ § 23, Onus, pp. 35–6.). In van Helmont’s philosophy there is a hierarchy of psycho-physical agents. Seeds are the most complex, they are matter-bound, whereas ferments are only by choice connected with matter. See ‘Imago fermenti’, §§ 12–13, Onus, pp. 113–4, cf. Pagel, van Helmont, pp. 72–3.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Trogymnasmata Meteori’, § 11, Ortus, p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Trogymnasmata Meteori’, §§ 19–20, Ortus, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  107. “Aqua enim vacuum non tolérât, ut neque sui compressionem, per aliquod movens comprimendo. Duntaxat inspissatione seminali comprimitur, per sui transmutationem formalem. Ex opposito autem, aer, sine vacuo subsistere nequit... ideoque sui compressionem, atque dilatationem tolerat.” (Trogymnasmata Meteori’, §§ 3–4, Ortus, p. 67).

    Google Scholar 

  108. “Si l’air rarifié a du vide? Respondeo affirmative, et in poris aeris est ether sive magnale, quod est medium inter corpus et non.” (van Helmont to Mersenne 15 January 1631, Mersenne, Correspondance, iii, p. 34.).

    Google Scholar 

  109. Van Helmont to Mersenne, 30 January 1631, Mersenne, Correspondance, iii, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Van Helmont to Mersenne, 11 January 1631, Merserme, Correspondance, iii, p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Van Helmont to Mersenne, 15 January 1631, Mersenne, Correspondance, iii, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  112. See ‘Complexionum atque Mistionum Elementalium Figmentum’, § 10, Ortus, p. 105, ‘Imago Fermenti Impregnat Massam Semine?’, § 7, ibid., p. 112 and ‘Tria Prima Chymicorum Principia’, ibid., pp. 398–412. Pagel stressed the anti-materialistic overtones of van Helmont’s criticism of the Paracelsian doctrine of principles, see Pagel, Van Helmont (n. 41), pp. 59–60.

    Google Scholar 

  113. ‘Tria Prima Chymicorum Principia’, § 58, Ortus, p. 408. For a detailed analysis of van Helmont’s views of mercury, see Newman, Gehennical Fire, pp. 146–51.

    Google Scholar 

  114. “Ego siquidem nudam lubens physicam aspicio ubique, non sane figuras; aut vires moventes in mathesi applico naturae”. (‘Imago Fermenti’, § 7, Ortus, p. 112.) See also van Helmont, ‘De lithiasi’, iv, §§ 11–12, Opuscula Medica Inaudita (Amsterdam, 1648, first edn: Cologne, 1644), pp. 34–5.

    Google Scholar 

  115. In 1651 Davidson moved to Poland, where he became physician to the Queen Maria Luisa Gonzaga. On Davidson see DSB; E.T. Hamy, ‘William Davidson, Intendant du Jardin du Roy et Professeur de Chimie (1647–51), Nouvelles Archives du Muséum d’Histoire Naturelle, 3e série, 10 (1898), 1–38; Metzger, Doctrines Chimiques, pp. 45–51; J. Read, ‘William Davidson, First Professor of Chemistry at the Jardin du Roi (1648)’, Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Sciences 30 (1951), 660–66; id., ‘William Davidson of Aberdeen. The First British Professor of Chemistry’, Ambix 9 (1961), 70–101; Partington, iii, pp. 4–7. J-P. Brach ‘Deux exemples de symbolisme géométrique dans des textes alchimiques du XVIIe siècle’, in D. Kahn and S. Matton (eds.), Alchimie. Art histoire et mythes (n. 14), pp. 717–35.

    Google Scholar 

  116. See Read (n. 112), 74; 77.

    Google Scholar 

  117. See Brach (n. 112). See also R. Halleux’s notes to Kepler’s L’Etrenne ou la neige sexangulaire (Paris, 1975), p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  118. W. Davidson, Philosophia Pyrotechnica, seu Cursus Chymiatricus (Paris, 16502), pp. 85–89; and 316.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Ibid., p. 316.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ibid., pp. 317–31.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Ibid., p. 326.

    Google Scholar 

  122. W. Davidson, Commentariorum in Sublimis Philosophi & Incomparabilis Viri Petri Severini Dani Ideam Medicinae Philosophicae Propediem proditorum Prodromus (The Hague, 1660).

    Google Scholar 

  123. Ibid., pp. 206–12.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Ibid., p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Ibid., pp. 258–61 and 363. Davidson’s experiments are taken mainly from Sennert and Sperling.

    Google Scholar 

  126. The bibliography on Gassendi is huge. An updated bibliography is to be found in S. Murr (ed.), Gassendi et l’Europe (Paris, 1997), pp. 467–92. An exception to the standard view is Bloch, who showed the presence of chemical themes in Gassendi’s philosophy, see O. Bloch, La Philosophie de Gassendi. Nominalisme, Matérialisme et Métaphysique (The Hague, 1971), pp. 252–9. The interpretation of Gassendi’s theory of matter as strictly mechanist is reiterated by M.J. Osier, Divine Will and the Mechanical Philosophy. Gassendi and Descartes on Contingency and Necessity in the Created World (Cambridge, 1994), pp. 196–8.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Syntagma Philosophicum, in Petri Gassendi Diniensis... Opera Omnia 4 vols (Lyons, 1658) [hereafter Opera Omnia], i, p. 265b. Cf. T. Gregory, Scetticismo ed empirismo. Studio su Gassendi (Bari, 1961), pp. 157–9.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Gassendi, Syntagma Philosophiae Epicuri, in Animadvertiones in Decimum Librum Biogenis Laertii (Lyons, 1649), repr. in Opera Omnia, iii, p. 19b. “Videlicet supponens motum (quern Democritus non negabat) convenire Atomis, absurdum censuit vim specialem ipsis non attribuere, qua talis motus cieretur: huiusmodi autem est gravitas, seu pondus, impulsiove, ac impetus, qua agi quicquid movetur, constat.” Ibid., p. 201.

    Google Scholar 

  129. ‘Dicimus deinde explodendum esse, quod Atomi a seipsis habeant vim motricem, seu impetum.’ Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 280.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Ibid., p. 273.

    Google Scholar 

  131. See Bloch (n. 123), pp. 268; and M. Messeri, Causa e Spiegazione. La Fisica di Pierre Gassendi (Milan, 1985), pp. 102–3.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, 277a.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 336a.

    Google Scholar 

  134. For Gassendi’s notion of molecule, see Bloch (n. 123), pp. 252–9; Messeri (n. 128), pp. 109–12; and H. Kubbinga, ‘La théorie moléculaire chez Gassendi’, in Quadricentenaire de la Naissance de Gassendi 1592–1992. Actes du Colloque International Pierre Gassendi. Digne-les-Bains, 18–21 Mai 1992, 2 vols. (Digne, 1994), ii, pp. 283–302.

    Google Scholar 

  135. “Heine ex atomis conformari primum moleculas quasdam inter se diversas, quae sint semina rerum diversarum.” Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 282b.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Philosophiae Epicuri Syntagma, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 25b.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Philosophiae Epicuri Syntagma, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 20a.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, pp. 241ab and 472a.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 472a.

    Google Scholar 

  140. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 245b.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Cf. Bloch (n. 123), pp. 258–9.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 39a.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, pp. 136a-b.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 114b. Emerton (n. 76), pp. 133–53.

    Google Scholar 

  145. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, 36b-37a. Cf. A.E. Shapiro, Fits, Passions, and Paroxysms. Physics, Method, and Chemistry and Newton’s Theories of Colored Bodies and Fits of Easy Reflections (Cambridge, 1993), pp. 40–8.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 37b.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 41 la.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, pp. 37b–38b and 41b–42a.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Georg Bauer (Agricola), De Ortu et Causis Subterraneorum (Basle, 1546).

    Google Scholar 

  150. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 114a: “Deinde non videntur etiam calor, & frigus necessaria agentia, a quibus lapides creentur. Neque enim qui lapides in fluviorum fundis gignuntur, ob calorem concrescunt; neque qui intra Animalia formantur, compinguntur a frigore: & neque aut stillicidia, quae lapidescunt, aut fontes, qui vertunt res diversas in lapides, id a calore, aut frigore habent, cum absque utrovis idem faciant.”

    Google Scholar 

  151. “... non videtur profecto posse tales lapides fieri ex massa indiscreta, & quam non pervadat spiritus quidam elaborator, a quo illa partium, particularumque tarn regularis distributio, & minorum in conformandis maioribus compactio fit.” Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 114b. “lam ergo Lapidificum germen in succo collecto intra receptaculum totam interius massam pervadens corpuscula ita coaptat, ut simul massam coagulet, figat, ipsique duo quaedam praestet, quae non possunt lacti praestari a coagulo. Unum, quod ipsam interea dispescat in plureis massulas, easque seu aequaleis, seu inaequaleis uniformiter configured habet id vero quatenus est non coagulum modo, verum etiam semen; idemque agit in materia lapidea intra conceptaculum, quod in materia triticea vis seminalis intra vaginam: nempe ut ex hac multa grana consimilia discernuntur, unde spica componitur; ita ex illa multi lapilli consimiles, unde contexitur rupicula gemmea.” Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 117b.

    Google Scholar 

  152. “Colorum autem varietas referenda videtur partim ad seminalem vim, quae contexturae corpuscula uti ad specialem configurationem; ita ad specialem colorationem attemperet; partim ad commistionem succorum, qui ex Terris, Succis concretis, Mineralibusque aliis quidpiam coloratum delibaverit.” Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 118a.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, pp. 277b; 334a and 386a.

    Google Scholar 

  154. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 172a–b. Gassendi maintains that the vegetative principle of plants (which is material) can be named anima only “ex analogia”, ibid., ii, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 171b. On salt as generative principle see Emerton (n. 76), pp. 209–226.

    Google Scholar 

  156. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 275a.

    Google Scholar 

  157. “Intelligi deinde potest Animam, quae in semine, prout ipsa quoque defluxit ex omnibus partibus esse & consciam nutricationis, animationis, constitutionis singularum adeo, ut cum iam sit animae totius quasi epitome, agere idem pergat in materiam seminis, quae est ipsa quoque epitome totius corporis...”, Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, iii, 275b. Cf. J. Roger, Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée française au XVIII e siècle (Paris, 19932), pp. 135–140.

    Google Scholar 

  158. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 262b. See also ibid, pp. 170b–171a, on the spontaneous generation of plants.

    Google Scholar 

  159. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, p. 334a.

    Google Scholar 

  160. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, i, 280b.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Petri Gassendi Theologi Epistolica Exercitatio...(Paxis, 1630), repr. as Examen Philosophiae Roberti Fluddi, in Opera Omnia, iii, pp. 211–268. See Gassendi to Peiresc 2 December 1628, and also Mersenne, Correspondance, i, pp. 61–2; ii, pp. 86–7 and 132–41. Mersenne had also asked van Helmont’s view of Fludd. Van Helmont’s judgement of Fludd is contained in a letter dated 19 December 1630, see Mersenne, Correspondance, ii, p. 584.

    Google Scholar 

  162. See F.A. Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition (London, 1964), pp. 434–40; L. Cafiero, ‘Robert Fludd e la polemica con Gassendi’, Rivista Critica di Storia della Filosofia, 19 (1964), 367–410, and ibid., 20 (1965), pp. 3–15, and J-C. Darmon, ‘Quelques enjeux épistémologiques de la querelle entre Gassendi et Fludd’, F. Greiner, Aspects de la tradition alchimique au XVII e siècle (Paris and Milan, 1998), pp.63–84.

    Google Scholar 

  163. On Fludd, see W.H. Huffman, Robert Fludd and the End of the Renaissance, (London, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  164. Gassendi, Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, pp. 231b–232a. On Fludd’s alchemical interpretation of the Scriptures see N.E. Emerton, ‘Creation in the thought of J.B. van Helmont and Robert Fludd’, in P. Rattansi and A. Clericuzio (eds.), Alchemy and Chemistry in the 16 th and 17 th Centuries (Dordrecht, 1994), pp. 85–101. For the Philosophia ad Athenienses, see Paracelsus, Sämtliche Werke, l. Abteilung: Medizinische, naturwissenschaftliche und philosophische Schriften, Hrsg. von K. Sudhoff, vols 1–14 (München-Berlin, 1922–33), vol. 13, pp. 387–423.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Gassendi rejects the doctrine of the ancient origins of alchemy, see Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, pp. 259a-b. Cf. A. Clericuzio, ‘Alchemia Vetus et Vera. Les théories sur l’origine de l’alchimie en Angleterre au XVIIe siècle’, in D. Kahn and S. Matton (eds.), Alchimie, art, histoire et mythes (n. 14), pp. 737–48. On the prisca sapientia see D.P. Walker, The Ancient Theology (London, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  166. “Capite iam tertio tuetur Consonantias suas Macrocosmicas. Ut concedam vero licere, Pytagoreorum exemplo, harmoniam quandam inter membra Mundi praecipua constituere: hoc tarnen videor posse dicere, non abesse a fabula quidquid de illa usquam somniatur. Etenim, ut Opifex Mundi rationem quandam habuit, cur hoc situ, hac mole, hac forma condiderit omnia; ita miselli homunculi videntur nimis temere rationem illam determinare.” Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 232a.

    Google Scholar 

  167. Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 236a.

    Google Scholar 

  168. Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 259a.

    Google Scholar 

  169. “Hac de re vero quidquid sit, existimo negari non posse, quin duo quaedam valde utilia cognitionis genera debeantur Alchymiae. Unum est circa Naturam. Etsi enim intimos usque rerum naturalium penetrare non liceat, ut ipsarum essentias, discrimina, vireis, actiones, & agendi modos, proportionem item, atque contexturam cum radicali, & propria singulorum causa dignoscamus: veruntamen si quidpiam ex iis, quae res quasque interne componunt, cognoscere concedatur, illud profecto isti Arti acceptum referendum est. Haec enim est, quae Naturae librum sola evolvit, ac perscrutatur, cum ceterae omnes superficie tenus naturalia considerent.” Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 259a.

    Google Scholar 

  170. Examen, Opera Omnia, iii, p. 259a.

    Google Scholar 

  171. Syntagma Philosophicum, Opera Omnia, ii, p. 140a.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Clericuzio, A. (2000). Spirit, Chemical Principles and Atoms in France in the First Half of the Seventeenth Century. In: Elements, Principles and Corpuscles. Archives Internationales D’Histoire des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 171. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9464-6_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9464-6_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5640-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9464-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics