Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Origins ((ORIN,volume 1))

Abstract

The importance and the frequency of the analogy between letters and atoms in ancient atomism are well known. The search for and the discovery of this analogy appear as an attempt to explain the coexistence of change and permanence in nature. But atomism was not the only corpuscular theory proposed with a view to solving this problem. Moreover, the comparison of nature or the world with letters and their combinations is also used elsewhere. It appears, for example, in connection with the theory of the four elements. But it seems to be in use here much later and with an exclusively illustrative or didactic function. The pseudo-Aristotelian De mundo compares the harmonious mixing of the elements in nature with the blending of colours in painting, of sounds in music, or of vowels and consonants in discourse1:

But [...] art as well, imitating nature, does so. For painting, mixing the natures of the colours white, black, yellow and red, furnishes images which resemble the preceding ones. Music, mixing in the same way sharp and low-pitched, long and short sounds, realizes a single harmony between different voices. And grammar, making a mixture of vocalic and consonantic letters, builds its whole art upon them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Aristoteles Latinus, De mundo, (5), 396 b 16–23, ed. W.L. Lorimer, Rome, Libr. dello Stato, 1951, p. 66. My translation.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. F. Desbordes, Idées romaines sur l’écriture, Lille, Presses Univ. de Lille, 1990, p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  4. On the linguistic concept of “double articulation”, cf. A. Martinet, La, Linguistique synchronique, Paris, P.U.F., 1974, chapter I.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf., in this volume, R. Harré e.a., “Apparatus as Models of Nature”, pp. 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Aristotle, On Generation and Corruption, 315 a 34 and 315 b 6–14, in Complete Works, revised Oxford translation, ed. by J. Barnes, Princeton, Princeton Univ. Press, 1985, vol. I, p. 514.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Aristotle, Metaphysics, 985 b 16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  8. M. Serres, La naissance de la physique dans le texte de Lucrèce. Fleuves et turbulences, Paris, Ed. de Minuit, 1977, p. 175. My translation.

    Google Scholar 

  9. R. Cadiou, “Atomes et éléments graphiques”, Bulletin de VAssociation G. Budé, oct. 1958, pp. 54–64.

    Google Scholar 

  10. As in the case of difference in tropè or thesis. The example of I and H appears in Philo of Alexandria, De aeternitate mundi, 22. But the manuscripts of the Aristotelian text mention also Z and N, N and H, or Z and H. For the difference in rhusmos or schema, the case of A and N is sometimes replaced by A and H.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cadiou (o.c.) suggests a runic or ogamic type.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. G. de Santillana, Le Origini del pensiero scientifico, Firenze, Sansoni, 1966, pp. 153, 157.

    Google Scholar 

  13. E. Benveniste, Problèmes de linguistique générale, Paris, Gallimard, 1966, p. 333.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 330.

    Google Scholar 

  15. H. Wismann, “Réalité et matière dans Tatomisme démocritéen”, in F. Romano (ed.), Democrito e l’atomismo antico (= Siculorum Gymnasium, n.s., XXXIII-1, 1980, p. 69: “Le terme de rhusmos (plus couramment rhuthmos) évoque d’abord le mouvement de l’eau, la succession régulière des ondes (voir le verbe rheiri)”. All other quotations come from the pp. 70–71. See also another article by H. Wismann, “Atomos Idea”, Neue Hefte für Philosophie, XV-XVI (1979), pp. 34–52.

    Google Scholar 

  16. For an overview of the etymology and the significations of these words, cf. F. Desbordes, o.c., chapter VII.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Translation from the Complete Works, vol. II, p. 2331. Cf. the comment in the edition of the Poetics by R. Dupont-Roc & J. Lallot, Paris, Seuil, 1980, p. 318.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. H. Maldiney, Aîtres de la langue et demeures de la pensée, Lausanne, L’Age d’Homme, 1975, pp. 338–341.

    Google Scholar 

  19. On the rhetorical and poetic effects of enargeia in general, cf. P. Galand-Hallyn, Les Yeux de l’éloquence, Orléans, Paradigme, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Lucretius systematically uses elementa to designate the letters. The De rerum natura has only one occurrence of littera (II, 292).

    Google Scholar 

  21. I quote the translation by M. Ferguson Smith, Cambridge (Mass.), Harvard Univ. Press; London, Heinemann, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  22. For a series of other examples, cf. P. Friedländer, “Pattern of Sound and Atomistic Theory in Lucretius”, American Journal of Philology, 1941, pp. 16–33.

    Google Scholar 

  23. As we saw, the stoikheion is the minimal unity of spoken as well as written language.

    Google Scholar 

  24. M. Bollack, La Raison de Lucrèce, Paris, Minuit, 1978, p. 246 (my translation). Cf. also the indications given by R. Galvagno, “Modello seiendfico e testo poetico: atomi e lettere in Lucrezio e Marchetti”, in Il segno barocco. Testo e metafora di una civiltà, ed. G. Nocera, Rome, Bulzoni, 1983, pp. 245–261. My analysis of the metaphor of writing in Lucretius does not of course aim at being complete. For a thorough study of different aspects of the question, cf. A. Deremetz, Le Miroir des Muses, Lille, Septentrion, 1995, pp. 242–288.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. H. Blumenberg, Die Lesbarkeit der Welt, Frankfurt, Suhrkamp, 1981, p. 40: “Die Buchstabenmetapher veranschaulicht zwar die reduktive Verfahrensweise der atomistischen Theorie, aber sie leistet nichts zu ihrer Begründung.”

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. De rerum natura, II, 700 sqq., and V, 837 sqq.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cicero, De natura deorum, II, 93, transi. H. Rackham, London, Heinemann; Cambridge (Mass.), Harvard Univ. Press, 1961, p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Two examples: Kepler, who in his De Stella nova reports a conversation with his wife on the subject (Gesammelte Werke, vol. I, ed. M. Caspar, Munich, Beck, 1938, pp. 238–286); and Chateaubriand, who inserts in the “notes et éclaircissements” of his Génie du christianisme a long development which should refute atomistic theories.

    Google Scholar 

  29. I, 227–228: “... whence does Venus restore living creatures to the light of life each after its kind...”.

    Google Scholar 

  30. II, 172–174: “... and in a word all else which divine pleasure, the guide of life, persuades men to approach, herself leading them and coaxing them, through the ways of Venus, to beget their generation, that the human race may not come to an end.”

    Google Scholar 

  31. “Etymological”, of course, in the ancient sense, not as practiced in modern linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  32. De rerum natura, IV, 836–841; V, 1041–1043.

    Google Scholar 

  33. De rerum natura, 1, 150: “nullam rem e nilo gigni divinitus umquam”; see also Epicurus’ Letter to Herodotus. And cf. the modern version by B. Russell (A History of Western Philosophy, New York, Simon & Schuster, 1963, p. 67): the question of the teleology of Creation is senseless, “since, to make it significant, we should have to suppose the Creator created by some super-Creator, whose purpose he served. The conception of purpose, therefore, is only applicable within reality, not to reality as a whole.”

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hallyn, F. (2000). Atoms and Letters. In: Hallyn, F. (eds) Metaphor and Analogy in the Sciences. Origins, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9442-4_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9442-4_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5559-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9442-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics