Skip to main content

Generative Experience of Time

  • Chapter
The Many Faces of Time

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 41))

Abstract

In1 this century the attempt has been undertaken to make progress with the longstanding problem of time by posing the question as to how time is originally experienced. I would like to take up anew this question, one posed above all by the first thinkers of phenomenology, Husserl and Heidegger. In my opinion a phenomenological theory of time can only then have a claim to binding knowledge when it arises out of an original experience of time. An original experience of time I understand as that experience through which we as human beings first notice that there is such a thing as “time,” an experience which may thus possibly occasion us to form the concept “time.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. Iwould like to thank my assistant, Dr. Felix Ó Murchadha, for his effort in translating this text into English.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. in this context the author’s “Heimwelt, Fremdwelt, die eine Welt,” in Phanomenologische Forschungen, ed. E. W. Orth, vol. 24, 1991, 313ff. and 320ff.

    Google Scholar 

  3. In relation to the inner connection of logos, time, and number cf. the author’s “Zeit als Zahl. Das Pythagoraische im Zeitverstandnis der Antike,” in Zeiterfahrung und Personalität, ed. P. Rohs (Frankfurt a.M., 1992).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. J. Stambaugh (Albany, 1996) [in the following cited as BT], 352.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Martin Heidegger, Der SatzvomGrund(Pfullmgen,1957), 181.

    Google Scholar 

  6. For a justifiably critical assessment of this cf. Ernst Tugendhat, Der Wahrheitsbegriff bei Husserl undHeidegger(Berlin, 1970), 368, footnote. Cf. in this regard too the author’s “Heidegger and the Principle of Phenomenology,” in Martin Heidegger. Critical Assessments, ed. Chr. Macann (London, 1992).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. Hans-Georg Gadamer, “Über leere und erfüllte Zeit,” in Kleine Schriften III(Tübingen, 1972), 221ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Aristotle, Politic , 1252a30ff.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. ibid., 1252b16.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The claim that man and woman are equal in the family for Aristotle and that this is for him an essential foundation for political equality may seem surprising. But apart from what I have presented in the main body of this article, the validity of this thesis is supported by a passage in the Nicomachean Ethics: 1160b32ff. Here Aristotle, in setting up an analogy between the good, thus non-despotic constitutions, and the relationship of friendship within the house, made a parallel between the friendly “benevolent” relationship between husband and wife and the relationship of equality, which in a Timocracy (which in turn because of its relationship with the polity or the—in this place favorably judged—democracy is positively assessed, cf. 1160bl7ff.) exists between the aristocratic power holders. In the same way as the latter in ruling a polis are equal to one another, so do the husband and wife rule with equal rank over the house.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf.Pol., 1252b5ff..

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. in this regard the author’s “Die Zweideutigkeit der Doxa und die Verwirklichung des modernen Rechtsstaats,” in Meinungfreiheit: Grundgedanken und Geschichte in Europa und USA, ed. J. Schwartländer und D. Willoweit, Tübinger Universitatsschriften, vol. 6: Forschungsprojekt Menschenrechte (Kehl a.Rh., 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1161a25ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. Pol., 1253b32/33..

    Google Scholar 

  15. In the Paris Manuscripts the young Marx interpreted the begetting of children as productive work and precisely in that falls victim to the barbarianism which Aristotle exposed. Thus the much praised humanism of the young Marx did not from the very beginning stretch very far. Admittedly, to the extent to which we have today become used to characterizing the begetting of children as “reproduction” of the human species, our own humanity does not fare much better.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit(Oxford, 1977), ch. IV: The Truth of Self-Certainty, 104ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition(Chicago, 1958), 175ff. and 246f. along with 96ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. BT, 40.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. H. Arendt.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. Plato, Symposium 206c ff.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. on this theme the author’s “Fundamental Moods and Heidegger’s Critique of Contemporary Culture,” in Reading Heidegger. Commemorations, ed. J. Sallis (Bloomington/Indianapolis, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  22. BT, 282 (§ 62) along with 219ff. (§§ 46–48) as well as 245f. and 277.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf. G. Marcel: Philosophie der Hoffnung(Munich, 1957), in particular: “Das Geheimnis der Familie,” 77ff. and “Die Schöpferische Verpflichtung als Wesen der Vaterschaft,” 143ff

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. BT, 343f.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The house (oikos), i.e., the living space of the family in antiquity on which Aristotle bases the explanation of the essential source of the polis, is not simply the elementary form of community, i.e., the form of community which is by nature not further analysable. It is rather the fusing of two forms of living with one another, which themselves are in this sense elementary: the ephemeral elementary community of master-servant and the generative elementary community of matrimony. (An “Element” is defined by Aristotle in Metaphysics, 1014b26ff. as that which is indivisible with respect to its specific quality.)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. ibid., 1160b27f.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cf.Pol., 1252bl8ff.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. G.W.F. Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, ed. J. Hoffmeister (Hamburg, 1955), 155 (§§158–181), especially §§158, 163, 170 and 173.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Held, K. (2000). Generative Experience of Time. In: Brough, J.B., Embree, L. (eds) The Many Faces of Time. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 41. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9411-0_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9411-0_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5581-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9411-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics