Skip to main content

On Identifying and Reconstructing a General Legal Theory

  • Chapter
Essays in Legal Theory

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 46))

  • 374 Accesses

Abstract

My purposes in this article are dual: to discuss some relatively neglected issues about the scope, aims, and methods of legal theory that arise out of, yet transcend, the differences between Professor Moore and myself, and to comment on some of Professor Moore’s criticisms of my book, Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory 1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. R. Summers, Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Moore, The Need for a Theory of Legal Theories: Assessing Pragmatic Instrumentalism. A Review Essay of Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory by Robert S. Summers, 69 Cornell L. Rev. 988 (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Id. at 1000, 1011

    Google Scholar 

  4. A/, at 1011.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Id. at 1000. Among the other significant misunderstandings are these: ( 1 ) Professor Moore says I merely organized my book around themes that interested the American pragmatic instrumentalists. I organized the book around themes of legal theoretic interest that con¬cerned these thinkers. (2) Professor Moore calls my reconstructed version of instrumentalist theory a Weltanschauung—a “world view.” But the tenets of instrumentalist theory are not, in the usual sense of the word a Weltanschauung. (3) Professor Moore suggests that extreme rule skepticism was widespread among the instrumentalists. It was not widespread among those theorists I selected for study in my book. See generally R. Summers, supra note 1, at ch. 6, 161–62. (4) Professor Moore says that a theory of change in the law is the nominal topic of my chapter 3. This is not so. The nominal as well as the substantial topic ofthat chapter is the general theory of law making. (5) Professor Moore remarks that in my book I do not recognize the weaknesses of the “what was done” theory of precedent. This is untrue. The reader should see my chapters 4, 5, and 6, especially pages 102–05,112–15. (6) Professor Moore says that I omit entirely any treatment of instrumentalist writings on facts and factual analysis in the law. Parts of chapters 1,3, and 6 are devoted to this, and I remark at pages 279–80 of my book that this is an important area of further inquiry that these thinkers opened up. (7) Professor Moore complains that I did not give enough emphasis to instrumentalist theories of interpretation. He adds, however, that these thinkers largely failed to articulate a theory of interpretation, a point I also make in my book at pages 153–54. (8) Professor Moore says I am unable to state “precisely” how values enter a theory of adjudication. On page 173, 1 do treat an important aspect of this, and I go into it more fully in an earlier article. See Summers, Two Types of Substantive Reasons: The Core of a Theory of Common-Law Justification, 63 Cornell L. Rev. 707 (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Moore, supra note 2, at 1011.

    Google Scholar 

  7. In the book I stated that: The virtues are impressive. Many of these theorists saw the importance of formulating a general theory of value. As instrumentalists they naturally saw how law is itself an expression of value. It might even be said that they reconceptualized law’s nature. They saw it as a set of practical social tools with specific uses and identifiable effects, rather than as an authoritative and formal body of preexisting precepts. Surely these alone were gigantic steps. Those who had gone before had drastically overstated the necessary limits of law’s efficacy. The instrumentalists corrected this, and at the same time introduced technological rationalism and an empiricist mentality into legal thought. They brought to the fore the element of personnel in the law and provided a devastating critique of formalism, especially as it afflicted judges. It is appropriate to say that the instrumentalists opened up several relatively new branches of legal theory (including some that even the percipient Bentham had missed). Among these were the nature and variety of the means at law’s disposal, the law’s varied and complex goals and goal structures, the element of personnel in law, and the limits of law’s efficacy. R. Summers, supra note 1, at 279 (emphasis in original).

    Google Scholar 

  8. In the book I stated that: Beginning with the vices, we can conclude that these theorists dwelled far too much, in their theorizing about values, on the merely quantitative maximizing of wants and interests (as conventionally given). They thus failed to give qualitative notions of the just, the right, and the good their due. In stressing the practical and “technological” aspects of law, they neglected its normative character. It is true that they unmasked judicial lawmaking, but they devoted too little attention to the norms that should govern it. They were also unduly change-minded and experimentalist. They did not work out a general theory of justification for common law cases or for cases involving written law. They were excessively means-minded, and failed to grasp fully how law can be understood in terms of a continuum of means and goals. They adopted restrictive models of law’s goals and means — models essentially behavioral in nature. They generally misdescribed the nature of the criteria of validity at work in our system, and insisted on a misleading and, in my view, unhealthy version of the doctrine that law and morals are separate. They espoused an untenable predictivism. They failed to see major differences between legal and machine technologies. They overstated the roles of coercion and force. And they were naive about the complexities and difficulties of determining law’s effects and social facts generally. These are not small failures. Yet many are failures of overemphasis or of neglect and can thus be remedied. Id. at 278–79.

    Google Scholar 

  9. It is a defect of my book that it does not include a summary of the leading tenets. For a more extended summary than the one I now offer, see Summers, Pragmatic Instrumentalism and American Legal Theory, 13 Rechtstheorie 257 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  10. R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  11. O.W. Holmes, The Common Law 41 (1881).

    Google Scholar 

  12. R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Llewellyn, À Realistic Jurisprudence — The Next Step, 30 Colum. L. Rev. 431, 464 (1930).

    Google Scholar 

  14. R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  15. M ch.4.

    Google Scholar 

  16. M at 112–15.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Aj.ch.6.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Is. Id ch. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Id ch. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  20. F. Cohen, The Problems of a Functional Jurisprudence, 1 Mod. L. Rev. 5, 8 (1937) (footnote omitted).

    Google Scholar 

  21. R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Id. at 62–66, 69–70, 74–78, 105–12, 161–74, 182–89, 193–201, 212–22, 227–35, 258–67.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See, e.g., W. at49–59,66–69,70–74,78–79,92–99,105–15,121–33,161–75,179–89,201–08,215–22,225–30,250–52.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf text accompanying infra note 159 (on “presentism”).

    Google Scholar 

  25. See, e.g., A.G.N. Flew, A Dictionary Of Philosophy 228 (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See generally Boyd, On the Current Status of the Issue of Scientific Realism, 19 Erkenntnis45 (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  27. The so-called legal realists might be called “realists” in literary parlance, for they were concerned with fidelity to real life and with the accurate representation of life.

    Google Scholar 

  28. See generally J. Bentham, The Works Of Jeremy Bentham (J. Bowring ed. 1843).

    Google Scholar 

  29. See generally R. Ihering, Law As A Means To An End (I. Husik trans. 1913). On Bentham’s possible influence on Ihering, see Coing, Bentham’s Bedeutung für die Entwicklung der Interessenjurisprudenz und der allgemeinen Rechtslehre, 54 Archiv Für Rechts- Und Sozialphilosohie 69 (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  30. There was also a rather different movement in Scandinavia called “legal realism”. See Hart, Scandinavian Realism, 17 Cambridge L.J. 233 (1959).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Professor Moore writes as if I referred only to the American theorists when I made this claim. The European instrumentalists also qualify as part of this tradition.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Moore, supra note 2, at 993.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Id at 988–89.

    Google Scholar 

  34. R. Summers, supra note 1, at 273, 279–80.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Id. at 38 (”Sometimes the American theorists carried the analysis rather far. More often, they merely gestured suggestively (yet unmistakably) in certain directions.”). See id. at 279–80.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Moore, supra note 2, at 1011.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See, e.g., works cited in R. Summers, supra note 1, at 288–90.

    Google Scholar 

  38. See supra note 22.

    Google Scholar 

  39. R. Summers, supra note 1, at 22–26, 269–70.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Id. at 269–70.

    Google Scholar 

  41. In fact, I know of no single notion in any other theory with similarly wide-ranging integrating properties. Some such properties are logical, some functional, and some otherwise.

    Google Scholar 

  42. I did not discuss this criterion in my book. See generally Nowell-Smith, Philosophical Theories, 48 Aristot. Soc. Proc. 165 (1948); Summers, Notes on Criticism in Legal Philosophy, in More Essays In Legal Philosophy 9–10 (R. Summers ed. 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  43. R. Summers, supra note 1, at ch. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Id. at 112–15.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Id. ch. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Id. chs. 3, 8, 9, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Id. chs. 11, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Id chs. 1,2.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Mat 143–44.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Id. ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Id ch. 3

    Google Scholar 

  52. M chs. 2, 3, 8,9, 10, 11,12.

    Google Scholar 

  53. M at 272.

    Google Scholar 

  54. The question of what properly qualifies as a general legal theory merits more extensive treatment than either Professor Moore or I have been able to give it here. The question is exceedingly complex and requires a book of its own.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Moore, supra note 2, at 1013.

    Google Scholar 

  56. M at 1012.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Id. at 1013.

    Google Scholar 

  58. I am indebted to my colleague Professor David Lyons for discussion of this point.

    Google Scholar 

  59. See, e.g. J. Austin, The Province Of Jurisprudence Determined (1832); H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law(1961); H. Kelsen, General Theory Of Law And State (1945).

    Google Scholar 

  60. See, e.g., T. Aquinas, Summa Theologica, in Selected Political Writings 52 (A.P. d’Entreves ed. 1959); 1 W. Blackstone, Commentaries On The Law Of England (W.C. Jones ed. 1976); H. Grotius, Prolegomena To The Law of War and Peace (F. Kelsey tr. 1957); S. Pufendorf, de Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo (H. Milford ed. 1934); Locke, An Essay Concerning the True Original, Extent and End of Civil Government, in The English Philosophers From Bacon To Mill 403, 503 (E. Burtt ed. 1939).

    Google Scholar 

  61. See, e.g., J.C. Carter, Law, Its Origin, Growth And Function (1907); H. Maine, Ancient Law (F. Pollock ed. 1906); F. von Savigny, Of The Vocation Of Our Age For Legislation And Jurisprudence ch. 2 (A. Hay ward ed. 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Moore, supra note 2, at 1011.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Id. at 993. It is not difficult to trace the origins of Moore’s conception. Professor Ronald M. Dworkin has written that a general theory of law, in its normative part, “must have a theory of legislation, of adjudication, and of compliance.” R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously vii (1978). Professor Dworkin goes on, however, to indicate that a general theory of law may also treat many other matters.

    Google Scholar 

  64. See, e.g., J. Austin, supra note 59.

    Google Scholar 

  65. See, e.g., H. Kelsen, supra note 59.

    Google Scholar 

  66. See H.L.A.Hart, supra note 59.

    Google Scholar 

  67. See works cited supra note 61.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Moore, supra note 2, at 1013.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Id. at 1002–10.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Id. at 1010.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Id. at 1013.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Id. 1003.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Id. at 1008.

    Google Scholar 

  74. An important exception is Jeremy Bentham. For his views on value, see J. Bentham, An Introduction To The Principles Of Morals And Legislation (Burns & Hart eds. 1970). For his general views on adjudication and fact finding, see Postema, The Principle of Utility and the Law ofProcedure: Bentham’s Theory of Adjudication, 11 Ga. L. Rev. 1393 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  75. Kelsen may be something of an exception. See R. Moore, Legal Norms And Legal Science ch. 4 (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  76. See generally A.P. d’Entreves, Natural Law (2d ed. 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  77. Moore, supra note 2, at 1010.

    Google Scholar 

  78. See supra p. 1022.

    Google Scholar 

  79. See, e.g., works cited supra notes 59–60.

    Google Scholar 

  80. R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Compare, for example, Pound, Common Law and Legislation, 21 Harv. L. Rev. 383 (1908) with H. Kelsen, Pure Theory Of Law 348–56 (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  82. See supra note 75.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Moore, supra note 2, at 1003.

    Google Scholar 

  84. R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  85. H. Kelsen, supra note 59, chs. X, Xl

    Google Scholar 

  86. H.L.A. Hart, supra note 59, chs. V, Vi (1961).

    Google Scholar 

  87. Moore, supranote 2, at 1005. See also R. Summers, supra note 1, at 54–56, 87–89, 146–47.

    Google Scholar 

  88. R. Summers, supra note 1, at 154–57; see also D. Lyons, Ethics And The Rule Of Law 92–95 (1984); Wilson, The Nature of Legal Reasoning: A Commentary with Special Reference to Professor MacCormick’s Theory, 2 Legal Stud. 269 (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  89. See Summers, supra note 5.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Moore, supra note 2, at 1010.

    Google Scholar 

  91. R. Summers, supra note 1, chs. 3,6, 11.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Moore, supra note 2, at 1002–13.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Id. at 1003.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Id. at 1004.

    Google Scholar 

  95. H.L.A. Hart, supra note 59, chs. V, Vi.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Moore, supra note 2, at 1005 (footnote omitted).

    Google Scholar 

  97. R. Summers, supra note 1, at 57, 112–15, 148–50.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Moore, supra note 2, at 1006–07.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Id. at 1007.

    Google Scholar 

  100. See, e.g., Pound, The Scope and Purpose of Sociological Jurisprudence (pts. 1–3), 24 Harv. L. Rev. 591 (1911), 25 Harv. L. Rev. 140 (1911), 25 Harv. L. Rev. 489 (1912).

    Google Scholar 

  101. See, e.g., Llewellyn, supra note 13, at 431.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Moore, supra note 2, at 993.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Id. at 1011.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Id. at 993–96.

    Google Scholar 

  105. See, e.g., Moore & Sussman, Legal and Institutional Methods Applied to the Debiting of Direct Discounts, 40 Yale L.J. 381 (1931).

    Google Scholar 

  106. See, e.g., Pound, supra note 100.

    Google Scholar 

  107. See H.L.A. Hart, supra note 59, at vii.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Hacker, Hart’s Philosophy of Law, in Law, Morality And Society: Essays In Honour Of H.L.A. Hart 1, 8 (P. Hacker & J. Raz eds. 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  110. H.L.A. Hart, supra note 59, ch. Iv.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Id. at 35–38.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Id. at 27–33.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Id. at 43–48.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Id. at 189–95.

    Google Scholar 

  115. This complex cluster of problems requires a separate essay.

    Google Scholar 

  116. See generally Hexner, The Timeless Concept of Law, 52 J. Politics 48 (1943).

    Google Scholar 

  117. Moore, supra note 2, at 998.

    Google Scholar 

  118. See generally Summers, The Technique Element in Law, 59 Calif. L. Rev. 733 ( 1971 ).

    Google Scholar 

  119. Hart has stated this in conversation on several occasions.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Raz, On the Functions of Law, in Oxford Essays In Jurisprudence 278 (A. Simpson ed. 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  121. See R. Summers, supra note 1, at 198–200.

    Google Scholar 

  122. See generally Hall, Conceptual ReformOne Task of Philosophy, 61 Aristot. Soc. Proc. 169(1961).

    Google Scholar 

  123. Moore, supra note 2, at 990.

    Google Scholar 

  124. See supra text accompanying notes 110–14.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Moore, supra note 2, at 994.

    Google Scholar 

  126. Id. at 997. It is interesting to contrast Moore’s view with that of Arnold Brecht: “Far greater efforts... should be diverted to the critical examination of goals and goal-values than have been in the past several decades. ...” Brecht, Political Theory: Approaches, in 12 International Encyclopedia Of The Social Sciences 307,313 (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  127. See R. Summers, Lon L. Fuller ch. 2 (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  128. R. Summers, supra note 1, at 66.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Moore, supra note 2, at 997 (footnote omitted).

    Google Scholar 

  130. For precisely this point, see Radin, Statutory Interpretation, 43 Harv. L. Rev. 863, 876–78(1930).

    Google Scholar 

  131. Moore, supra note 2, at 997.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Id. at 996.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Id. at 996–97. For a more elaborate account of this conception of taxonomy, see Tiryakian, Typologies, in 16 International Encylopedia Of The Social Sciences 177, 177–80(1968).

    Google Scholar 

  135. Moore, supra note 2, at 996.

    Google Scholar 

  136. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Id.at 997.

    Google Scholar 

  138. H.L.A. Hart, supra note 59, at 32 (emphasis in original).

    Google Scholar 

  139. Moore, supra note 2, at 997.

    Google Scholar 

  140. See Llewellyn, Some Realism About RealismResponding to Dean Pound, 44 Harv. L.Rev. 1222(1931).

    Google Scholar 

  141. There is a rapidly growing literature on the methodology and the pros and cons of reconstruction. See, e.g.,The History Of Ideas (P. King ed. 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  142. As I pointed out in my book, my ultimate interest was “aggregative.” The book concentrated on theorists as members of a collectivity sharing certain tenets. See R. Summers, supra note 1, at 13.

    Google Scholar 

  143. I frequently pieced together the positions of individual theorists from different sources, as manyof those thinkers were not very systematic. See R. Summers, supra note 1, at 25.

    Google Scholar 

  144. See supra pp. 1019–21.

    Google Scholar 

  145. For a listing of these extreme views, see supra p. 1020.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Moore, supra note 2, at 999–1000.

    Google Scholar 

  147. M at 1001.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Id

    Google Scholar 

  150. Id. at 1001–02.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Id. at 1002.

    Google Scholar 

  152. Id. at 989.

    Google Scholar 

  153. Id. at 1003.

    Google Scholar 

  154. The instrumentalists were interested in standards of validity, see R. Summers, supra note 1, ch. 4, in facts and descriptions of facts, see id. ch. 6, in theories of interpretation and precedent, see id. ch. 6, and in the theory of value, see id. ch. 1. They were not much concerned with the role of formal logic in legal reasoning. It cannot be said, though, that these theorists synthesized the foregoing interests into what Moore might call a “unified” theory of adjudication.

    Google Scholar 

  155. Quentin Skinner has explained better than could I why it would be wrong to “reconstruct” such answers. See Skinner, Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas, 8 Hist. & Theory 3 (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  156. Moore, supra note 2, at 1001.

    Google Scholar 

  157. Mat 1002.

    Google Scholar 

  158. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  159. “Presentism” has now become something of a name for a diverse cluster of views emphasizing currency as the criterion of relevance. See, e.g., Hall, In Defense ofPresentism, 18 Hist. & Theory 1 (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  160. Moore, supra note 2, at 989.

    Google Scholar 

  161. Moore, supra note 2, at 1010.

    Google Scholar 

  162. See, e.g., S. Nagel, Public Policy: Goals, Means, And Methods (1984); D. Mazmanian & P. Sabatier, Implementation And Public Policy (1983).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Summers, R.S., McRoberts, W.G., Goodhart, A.L. (2000). On Identifying and Reconstructing a General Legal Theory. In: Essays in Legal Theory. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 46. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9407-3_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9407-3_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5481-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9407-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics