Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 39))

  • 178 Accesses

Abstract

This study is an attempt at a comparative analysis of directives, optatives, and value statements from the point of view of the philosophy of language. The standpoint represented here is that there are certain general features of language independent of those of the particular languages and that there are such general features specific of the area of the statements in question. Our approach to the problem of these features will not be an a priori one, we shall pay strict attention to the facts of natural languages while making resort to some reconstructionist devices.1 Vital syntactic-semantic problems will be involved here, but nevertheless, an important role has to be ascribed to the pragmatic analysis as a tool indispensable in dealing with statements of these particular kinds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Comp. the approach to the philosophy of language outlined by J.R. Searle, Speech Acts. An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge 1969, ch. I.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Comp. A. Ross, Directives and Norms, London 1968, p. 1 f

    Google Scholar 

  3. R. Carnap, A. “Kaplan on value judgments”, in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. by P.A. Schilpp, La Salle-London 1963, p. 999 f.

    Google Scholar 

  4. K. Opatek, “The problem of `directive meaning”’, in Festskrift ti! Professor, Dr. Jur. et Phil. Alf Ross, Kobenhavn 1969, p. 405 f.

    Google Scholar 

  5. K. Opalek, “On the logical-semantic structure of directives”, Logique et Analyse XIII, 49–50, 1970, p. 188 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. A. Ross, op. cit., p. 120.

    Google Scholar 

  7. G.H. von Wright, Norm and Action. A Logical Enquiry, London 1963, p. 86.

    Google Scholar 

  8. A. Ross, op. cit., p. 123 f

    Google Scholar 

  9. K. Opalek, Prawo podmiotowe (The Subjective Law), Warszawa 1957, ch. III.

    Google Scholar 

  10. L. Petra2ycki, Teoria prawa i paristwa w zwiqzku z teoriq moralnosci (Theory of Law and State in Connection with Theory of Morals), Vol. I, Warszawa 1959, p. 70 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Comp. S. Wronkowska, “O znaczeniu i socjotechnicznej roll terminu `czyje§ prawo”’ (“On the meaning and sociotechnical role of the term `somebody’s right”’), Paristwo i Prawo (State and Law), 6, 1969, p. 1079 if.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Comp. G.H. von Wright, An Essay in Deontic Logic and the General Theory of Action, Amsterdam 1968, p. 13 f.

    Google Scholar 

  13. On some of the difficulties involved here comp. G.H. von Wright, “Deontic logic and the theory of conditions”, Critica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofia II, 6, 1968, p. 4 f

    Google Scholar 

  14. It would seem hardly acceptable to regard, e.g., -W or -W-, as concepts analogous to permission.

    Google Scholar 

  15. They are discussed, to some extent, by A. Ross, op. cit., pp. 38–60, this being rather exceptional.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Comp. O. Weinrerger, “Die Sollsatzproblematik in der modernen Logik”, Rozpravy Ceskoslovenske Akademie Véd, 68, 9, 1958; N. Rescher, The Logic of Commands, London-New York 1966, eh. III; A. Ross, op. cit., p. 71 tT.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Comp., e.g., A.N. Prior, Formal Logic, Oxford 1955; A.R. Anderson, “The formal analysis of normative systems”, Techn. Rep. No 2, Contract No SAR/Nour — 609/16/, Office of Naval Research, Group Psychology Branch, New Haven 1956; G.H. von Wright, An Essay..., cit. above; E. Stenius, “The principles of a logic of normative systems”, Acta Philos. Fennica XVI, 1963, p. 248 f

    Google Scholar 

  18. Comp. e.g., C. Wellman, The Language of Ethics, Cambridge Mass. 1961, eh. II-V.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Comp. G.H. von Wright, “The logic of practical discourse”, in Contemporary Philosophy. A Survey, ed. by R. Klibansky, Firenze 1968, p. 143 f

    Google Scholar 

  20. Comp., phanomenologiseh begrandeten Rechts-und Staatslehre, Leipzig 1924, p. 102 f; K. Opalek, Prawo podmiotowe, cit. above, p. 284 II:

    Google Scholar 

  21. Comp. A.P. Brogan, “The fundamental values universal”, Jour. of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Method, XVI, 1919; S. Hallden, “On the logic of `better”’, Uppsala 1957; R.M. Chisholm, E. Sosa, “On the logic of `intrinsically better”’, Amer. Philosophical Quarterly III, 16, 1966; G.H. von Wright, “The logic of practical discourse”, cit. above, p. 144 f

    Google Scholar 

  22. Comp. J. Lande, Studia z filozofhi prawn (Studies in Legal Philosophy), Warszawa 1959, p. 765 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  23. The first attempt seems to be that of K. Menger, “A logic of the doubtful. On optative and imperative logic”, Ergebnisse eines mathematischen Kolloquiums, S. II, 1, 1939.

    Google Scholar 

  24. R. Carnap, op.cit., p. 1005.

    Google Scholar 

  25. R. Carnap, op. cit., p. 1001 f., 1011 f.

    Google Scholar 

  26. This matter is discussed below, II, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  27. The term “theme” adopted from A. Ross, op. cit., p. 107.

    Google Scholar 

  28. On the term “happening” comp. T. Kotarbinski, Elementy teorii poznania, logiki folmalnej i metodologii nauk, Lwów 1929, p. 61 f. In the sense accepted by us it is in common use in the doctrinal study of law.

    Google Scholar 

  29. The last term will be left undefined.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Comp. K. Opalek, “On the logical-semantic structure of directives”, cit. above, p. 191 f.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Comp. G.H. von Wright, An Essay..., cit. above, p. 16 (in comparison with the first construction of a system of deontic logic by this author, “Deontic logic”,Mind LX, 1951); comp. R. Ross’s concept of the “idea of topic”, op.cit., p. 9 ff., and discussion by K. Opalek, “On the logical-semantic structure of directives”, cit. above, p, 178 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  32. In order to simplify matters we shall not discuss in this connection the problem of the “fabulating discourse” (comp. A. Ross, op.cit., p. 29 f1) which could enter here.

    Google Scholar 

  33. According to T. Czetowski, Filozofia na rozdrozu (Philosophy on Crossroads), Warszawa 1965, p. 119 f. Value statements are modal statements of some particular sort.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Comp. W. Van Orman Quine, Elementary Logic, rev. ed., Cambridge Mass. 1966, par. 8, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  35. On the ut, and that (German “dass”, French “que”) connectives, comp. K. Opalek, “On the logical-semantic structure of directives”, cit. above, p. 188.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibidem, p. 189 f.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Comp. — on the one hand — R. Catnap’s view in Philosophy and Logical Syntax, London 1935, p. 24, that of Ch.L. Stevenson in Facts and Values. Studies in Ethical Analysis, New Haven and London 1963, eh. II, and that of A. Ross, op.cit., p. 37 f; comp. — on the other hand — C. Well-man’s analyses of the evaluative, directive and critical meaning (op.cit., eh. VIII-X).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Comp., e.g., J. Lande, op. cit., p. 786 f; on the concept of instrumental goodness — G.H. von Wright, The Varieties of Goodness, ed. II, London 1964, eh. II.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Teleological directives (rules, norms) were frequently discussed, while teleological optatives were never mentioned. An example of the optative statement of this kind can be: “May we have fine weather tomorrow in order to make the trip we are planning”.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Comp. the remarks of J. Wolenski, “Spur o znaczenie normatywne” (“Contention on the subject of `normative meaning”’), in Naturalistyczne i antynaturalistyczne interpretacje humanistyki (The Naturalistic and Antinaturalistic Interpretation of Humanities), Poznan 1966, and those of J. Wróblewski, “The problem of the meaning of the legal norm”, Osterr. Zeitschr f Off Recht XIV, 3–4, 1964, p. 254 i, comp. also the discussion of Ch.L. Stevenson, op.cit., eh. IX, and M. Black, “Some questions about emotive meaning”, The Philosophical Rev. 57, 1948, on “strictly evoking”, “strictly designating”, “suggesting a thought”. Comp. also W. Alston, Philosophy of Language, Englewood Cliffs 1964, p. 10 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. K. Opalek, “The problem of `directive meaning”’, cit. above, p. 420.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Here the contributions of the ordinary language philosophy have to be stressed. Comp. J. Austin, How to Do Things with Words, London 1962, lect. VIII ff.

    Google Scholar 

  43. This holds true also in the case when a person establishes a directive for himself, and in the instance of conditional directives determining a “proper” (valid, etc.) way of conduct as means of attaining an end in case a person decides to pursue this end (e.g., the norms determining the way of contracting marriage, or of carrying out a sale — and purchase deed).

    Google Scholar 

  44. On the concept of “wish” comp. G.H. von Wright, “On the logic of some axiological and epistemological concepts”, in Ajatus XVII, 1952, p. 213 ff

    Google Scholar 

  45. The “types of addressing” were analysed by S. Frydman, “Dogmatyka prawa w §wietle socjologii” (“Doctrinal study of law in the light of sociology”), Ogólna nauka o prawie (General Science of Law), ed. B. Wróblewski, Vol. I, Wilno 1936, p. 146 ff

    Google Scholar 

  46. Comp. in this connection A. Ross, op.cit., p. 123 f; K. Opalek, J. Wróblewski, Zagadnienia teorii prawa (Problems of Legal Theory), Warszawa 1969, p. 107 f.

    Google Scholar 

  47. K. Opalek, “On the logical-semantic structure of directives”, cit. above, p. 187 f

    Google Scholar 

  48. Fulfilment“ (”satisfaction“) in this sense in A. Hofstadter, J.C.C. McKinsey, ”On the logic of imperatives“, Philosophy of Science, Oct. 1939, p. 446 ff: J. Wróblewski, I.c.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Such statements are termed “relational statements” — comp. J. Wróblewski, “Zwroty stosunkowe — wypowiedzi o zgodnosci z nonna” (“Relational statements — statements on conformity with norm”), Zeszyty Naukowe Uniw. Lódzkiego (The Lodi Univ. Review) 62, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  50. o F. Studnicki, “Traffic signs”, Semiotica II, 2, 1970, p. 164 ff., introduces the concept of “normative states of affairs” fulfilling normative statem ents. Criticism by K. Opalek, “The problem of directive meaning”, cit. above, p. 414, same author, “The problem of the existence of the norm”, Festschrift fir Adolf J. Merkl, München 1970, p. 293 f.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Attention has to be paid in this connection to the remarks of M. Black, “Analysis of rules” in Models and Metaphors. Studies in Language and Philosophy, Ithaca 1962, p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Comp. K. Opalek, “The complexity of law and of the methods of its study”, Scientia. Revue Internationale de Synthese Scientifique, CIV, 5–6, 1969, p. 287; same author, “Law as social phenomenon”, Archiv fur Rechts and Sozialphilosophie, 1, 1971, p. 47 f.

    Google Scholar 

  53. R. Carnap, Philosophy and Logical Syntax, cit. above, par. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Comp. E Studnicki, Przeplyw ih formacji o normach prawa (The Flow of Information on Legal Norms), Krakow 1965, in connection with the problem of the effectiveness of the legal norms, p. 35 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Comp. A. Ross, op.cit., par. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Comp. J. Nowacki, “O rodzajach ocen ze wzgedu na norme” (On the kinds of value statements based on norms), Zeszyty Naukowe Uniw. Lódzkiego (The Lódz Univ. Review) 14, 1959, p. 19 ff., and the literature cited there.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Such relational statements, however, appear in the role of components of the statements of the latter kind, comp. J. Wróblewski, “Statements on the relation of conduct and norm”, Logique et Analyse, XIII, 49–50, 1970, p. 157 f.

    Google Scholar 

  58. It is rather striking that the value statements are quite often reconstructed as conjunctions of descriptive and some sui generis (directive, optative, etc.) statements. When adopting such a course, it would seem invitng to try, e.g., to define the statement that something is good as a hypothetical or disjunctive optative, so that:

    Google Scholar 

  59. Understanding is surely a pragmatic concept, and not a semantic one. Our opinion differs here from that of J. Wróblewski, “The problem of the meaning of the legal norm”, op.cit., p. 262 tf.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Comp. Ch.L. Stevenson, op.cit., p. 21 f. (“laudatory”–“derogatory”).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Comp. K. Opalek, “Some problems of the theory of norms”, Logique et Analyse XII, 1969, p.91ff

    Google Scholar 

  62. On the character of legal reasonings comp. “Le raisonnement juridique et la logique déontique, Actes du Colloque de Bruxelles (23–25 Dec. 1969), esp. the paper by G. Kalinowski, ”Le raisonnement juridique et la logique juridique“, and the standpoint represented by Ch. Perelman, Logique et Annlyse XIII, 49–50, p. 3 fT, 25 W, 52 f, and passim.

    Google Scholar 

  63. This problem is widely discussed, and at least some directives (axiological norms) are said to be in some sense secondary to value statements. G.H. von Wright, An Essay..., cit. above, p. 12, inclines “(...) towards a position according to which value are basic and primary, norms derivative and secondary. Norms, according to this view, are often said to be instrumental towards realization of some values”. Our analysis leads to different results.

    Google Scholar 

  64. G.H. von Wright, Norm and Action, cit. above, p. 14 f.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Woleński, J. (1999). Directives, Optatives, and Value Statements. In: Woleński, J. (eds) Kazimierz Opałek Selected Papers in Legal Philosophy. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 39. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9257-4_18

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9257-4_18

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5230-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9257-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics