Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 39))

Abstract

The term “directive” (or “directive statement”) is used here in a broad sense, comprising norms, commands, requests, exhortations, suggestions, advice, rules (e.g., of games), and the like.1 One would be tempted to say that they are“directive statements”, having the same general kind of meaning (the “directive meaning”)2. The directives, as we see, are variously termed: a fact testifying to their differentiation. The terms mentioned above are, however, vague, and not apt to buildup a proper classification of directives. The classification which would be of interest to us would involve distinguishing, among directives, some groups of statements with peculiar kinds of meaning, constituting the subspecies of directive meaning. This matter, however, is not a simple one.3 For our analyses the general concept of directive meaning will suffice, together with roughly pointing to the extensiveness of the range of statements covered by the term “directive” and to their differentiation, to avoid some limitations of the analysis, not infrequently noted in this field.4

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The use of the term “directive” is analogous in A. Ross, Directives and Norms,London 1968 (but different as to the relation between directives and norms, par. 20 f).

    Google Scholar 

  2. K. Opalek, “The problem of `directive meaning”’, in Festkr/t til Professor, Dr. Jur. et Phil. Alf Ross,Copenhagen 1969, these volume pp..

    Google Scholar 

  3. Comp. R. Carnap, “A. Kaplan on value judgments”, in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap,ed. P.A. Schilpp, (The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. IX), La Salle-London 1963, pp. 1011 f. (with respect to the larger category of “optative statements”, comprising, among others, directives). Comp. the classifications of directives (nouns) in G.H. von Wright, Norm and Action,London 1963, ch. 1., A. Ross, op. cit., par. 10 if.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Here we have in mind the ways of analysis frequent in legal theory, concentrating on legal norms only.

    Google Scholar 

  5. R. Suszko, Zarys elementarnej skladni logicznej ( An Outline of the Elementary Logical Syntax ), Warszawa 1957, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Comp. e.g., C. Wellman, The Langunge of Ethics,Cambridge Mass. 1961, ch. 9, 10, and p. 290; differently O. Weinberger, “Die Sollsatzproblematik in der modernen Logik”, Rozpravy C K eskoslovenské Akademie Ved,68, 9, 1958, p. 1 f.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Comp. E.J. Lemmon, “Deontic Logic and the Logic of Lnperatives”, Logique et Analyse,VIII, 29, 1965, pp. 44 if..

    Google Scholar 

  8. As for the analogous problem with respect to value statements see R.G. Brown, I.M. Copi, Don E. Dulaney, W.K. Frankena, P. Heide, Ch.L. Stevenson, Language, Thought, and Culture,Ann Arbor, 1959, pp.149 f. On normative names J. Wróblewski, Zagadnienia teorii wykladni prawa ludowego (Problems of the Theory of Interpretation of the Socialist Law), Warszawa 1960, part. I.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Comp. J. Lande, Studia z filozofii prawa (Studies in Legal Philosophy), Warszawa 1959, pp. 930 f.

    Google Scholar 

  10. J. Wróblewski, “Zagadnienia zastowania maszyn matematycznych w prawoznawstwie” (Problems of applying computers to legal science), Studia Prawno-Ekonomiczne (Legal-Economic Studies), Vol. I, Lódz 1968, pp. 50 ft: Comp. e.g. J. Wolenski, “Spór o `znaczenie normatywne”’. (Contentention on the subject of `normative meaning’), in Naturalislyczne i antynaturalistyczne interpretacje humanistyki (The Naturalistic and Antinaturalistic Interpretations of Humanities), Poznan 1966, pp. 4 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Discussed in O. Weinberger, op. cit., passim; E.J. Lemmon, op. cit., 55 fï’; G.H. von Wright, “The logic of practical discourse”, in Contemporary Philosophy. A Survey, ed. by R. Klibansky, Firenze 1968 pp. 153

    Google Scholar 

  12. The same distinction, based on some conceptions of ordinary language philosophy, was proposed by E. Studnicki in a discussion of the problems of “directive meaning” in the Department of Legal Theory of Cracow University, in October 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  13. These formulas are only provisional; they will be rectified in the course of our analyses (comp. below 14.4 fi).

    Google Scholar 

  14. The view of I. Hedenius, discussed below (10) is related to (d), but more complicated.

    Google Scholar 

  15. O, Winberger, op. cit., and “Können Sollsätze (Imperative) als wahr bezeichnet werden?”, in the same issue of Rozpravy…,pp. 146 ft; N. Rescher, The Logic of Commands,London — New York 1966, pp. 38 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  16. A. Ross, op. cit., par. 4,5,9.

    Google Scholar 

  17. C.H. Langford, M. Langford, “Introduction to logic”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,1953, p. 565, discussed by A. Ross, op. cit., pp. 71 f.

    Google Scholar 

  18. A. Ross, op. cit., pp. 14, 17 f., 71 (comp. R.M. Hare, The Language ofMorals,Oxford 1952, pp. 18 f).

    Google Scholar 

  19. L Hedenius, “Befalningsatser, nonner och värdeutsagor (Commands, norms and value — propositions), in Nordist Sommeruniversitet,1954, cf. A. Ross, op. cit., pp. 32 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  20. A. Ross, op. cit., S 4; H.G. Brown, I.M. Copi, Don E. Dulaney, W.K. Frankena, P. Henle, Ch.L. Stevenson, op. cit., Ch. 5 ang 6.

    Google Scholar 

  21. K. Ajdukiewicz, O znaczeniu wyraien ( On the Meaning of Linguistic Expressions ), Lwów 1931, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Comp. H. Kelsen, Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts. Beitrag zu einer reinen Rechtslehre,Tübingen 1920, p. 99; A. Ross, Kritik der sogenannten praktischen Erkenntnis. Zugleich prolegomena zu einer Kritik der Rechtwissenschaft,Kopenhagen — Leipzig 1933, pp. 52 if.., and Towards a Realistic Jurisprudence. A Criticism of the Dualism in Law,Copenhagen 1946, pp. 39 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  23. G.H. von Wright, “An essay in deontic logic and the general theory of action, Acta Philosophica Fennica, XXI, Amsterdam 1968, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  24. d (“so it ought to be”) can also be predicated only of a sentence, not of a name.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Comp. K. Ajdukiewicz, “Zwiazki skladniowe miçdzy czlonami zdan oznajmujäcych” (Syntactical relations between the components of indicative sentences), in Jgzyk i poznanie (Language and Cognition), Vol. II, Warszawa 1965, pp. 345 if

    Google Scholar 

  26. Comp. J. Wolenski op. cit., and, J. Wróblewski, “The problem of the meaning of the legal norm”, Österreichische Zeitschrift fair öffentliches Recht,XIV, 3–4, 1964, pp. 254 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Here we have in mind the problem connected with customary rules, e.g., customary law: according to some views, the obligation to do something can be inferred from the fact that members of the group used to do it regularly in previous times.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Comp.

    Google Scholar 

  29. R. Carnap, op. cit., p. 1002.

    Google Scholar 

  30. It seems hardly justified to speak about the “conjunction” of a value statement and a descriptive statement; the meaning of directives seems to consist in something different from the meaning of value statements.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Comp. the discussion on ought entails can in (G.H. von Wright, Norm and Action,cit. above, ch. VII; E.J. Lemmon, op. cit., pp. 47 ff; R.M. Hare, Freedom and Reason,Oxford 1963, pp. 51 fI:

    Google Scholar 

  32. E. Stenius, “The principles of a logic of normative systems”, in Acta Philosophica Fennica, XVI, 1963, Proceedings of a Colloquium on Modal and Many-Valued Logics, Helsinki, 23–26 August, 1962, p. 248.

    Google Scholar 

  33. G.H. von Wright,An Essay…,cit. above, pp. 14, 16 (and similarly A.R. Anderson and A.N. Prior, cit. there). Compare on this subject G. Kalinowski, “Introduction à la logique juridique”, Bibliotheque de Philosophie du Droit,Vol. VIII, Paris 1965, pp. 82 ff

    Google Scholar 

  34. R. Carnap, op. cit., p. 1004 ff

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. G.H. von Wright, The logic of practical discourse, cit. above pp. 144 ff.; An Essay…, cit. above, pp. 13 f “Deontic logic”, Mind, 60, 1951, and “Deontic logics”, American Philosophical Quarterly 4, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Sometimes O (0) is used as basic, permission being defined as (- O —) — D —, 0), cf. e.g., E.J. Lemmon, op. cit., p. 40; on the relations between P-concepts and O-concepts cf. G.H. von Wright, An Essay…,cit. above, pp. 22 fl:, 34 if

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cf. E.J. Lemmon, op. cit., pp. 43 f.

    Google Scholar 

  38. The ut comes close to “utinam” in optative statements, cf. R. Carnap, op. cit., pp. 1004 f Optative statements have to some extent been analysed by K. Menger, “A Logic of the doubtful. On optative and imperative logic”, Ergebnisse eines mathematischen Kolloquiums,S. II, I, 1939.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Comp. J. Nowacki, “O rodzajach ocen ze wzglgdu na nonnq” (On the kinds of value statements based on norms), Zeszyty Naukowe Uniwersvtetu Lódzkiego (The Lódz University Review), S. I, No 14, 1959, pp. 20 ff

    Google Scholar 

  40. b1 this connection of R. Montague, “Syntactical treatments of modality, with corollaries on reflexion principles and finite axiomatizability”, Acta Philosophica Fennica,XVI, 1963, pp. 153 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. W. van Orman Quine, Elementary Logic,rev. ed., Cambridge Mass. 1966, p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf. notes 28 and 30.

    Google Scholar 

  43. K. Opalek, op. cit., pp…; Cf. also M. Black, “The analysis of rules”, in Models and Metaphors. Studies in Language and Philosophy, Ithaca 1962, p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Cf. G.H. von Wright on the logic of change in Norm and Action,cit. above, ch. II, pp. 28 f, and on the relation of act to change, ibid., eh. II, pp. 42 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf. A. Ross, Directives and Norms,cit. above, par. 10, 11, 12, and p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Attempts have been made in the legal field to discuss “stronger” and “weaker” norms on the basis of a graduation of their pragmatic function, cf. N. Bobbio, “Due variazioni sul tema dell’imperativismo”, in Atti del IV Congresso Nazionale di Filosofia del Diritto,Milano 1960; “Per una classificazione degli imperativi giuridici”, in Scritti giuridici in memoria di Piero Calamandrei, v. V, Padova 1956; “Comandi e consigli”, in Raccolta dei scritti in onore di Arturo Carlo Jemolo, v. IV, Milano; “Norma giuridica”, in Novissimo Digesto Italiano,Torino, pp. 19–23.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Cf. J. Lande, op. cit., pp. 924 f.; O. Weinberger, “Einige Betrachtungen über die Rechtsnorm vom Standpunkt der Logik and der Semantik”, Logique et Analyse, 28, 1964, p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Cf. M. Black, op. cit., pp. 107 f.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Cf. A. Ross, Directives and Norms,pp. 107 tl:

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Woleński, J. (1999). On the Logical-Semantic Structure of Directives. In: Woleński, J. (eds) Kazimierz Opałek Selected Papers in Legal Philosophy. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 39. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9257-4_16

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9257-4_16

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5230-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9257-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics