Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 43))

  • 159 Accesses

Abstract

One of the main concerns in contemporary legal philosophy involves the idea of law-imposed duty and its relevance for action. The interest in this topic is reflected in the discussion of a great variety of problems, all focused on the practical nature of the law. Its analysis presupposes a context of discourse somewhat wider than that of legal theory, and a more general philosophical discussion. The practical relevance of the law has been a subject of reflection in moral philosophy as well as in action theory. Each one of these lines of work has contributed valuable insights into the meaning of ‘duty’, the possibility of its justification, and its relationship with action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. For the sake of simplicity, hereafter, the expressions ‘reasons as premises of an argument’ and ‘premise-masons’ will be used interchangeably.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Moser, Paul K., Introduction, in: id. (ed.), A Priori Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press 1987, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. Cohen, Moms R., A Preface to Logic, New York: Henry Holt 1945, ch. I.

    Google Scholar 

  4. On this point, there are two opposing positions. One holds that the two meanings of truth are mutually independent; the other one sees only a gradual difference between them. For the first view, cf., e. g., Carnap, Rudolf, Introduction to Symbolic Logic and its Applications, New York: Dober 1958; id., Intellectual Autobiography, in: Path Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court 1963; Lewis, C. I., An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court 1971. For the second, cf. Quine, W. V. O., Two Dogmas of Empiricism, in: id., From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1953; Pap, Arthur, Semantics and Necessary Truth, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. on this subject, e. g., Whitehead, Alfred N., The Function of Reason, Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. Bunge, Mario, La ciencia, su método y su filosofia, Buenos Aires: Siglo X XI 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  7. For instance, the Kantian position that there are synthetic truths a priori in the physical as well as in the moral realm.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Audi, Robert, Practical Reasoning, London: Routledge 1991, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., pp. 68–72.

    Google Scholar 

  10. This leaves open the possibility that such contents are of a propositional or a non-propositional kind. This subject will be treated in Chapter III, in the context of reasons understood as premises of practical arguments.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Those who have written about this question usually identify rational states with beliefs. In this first part of the book, I will present several proposals, but will not question that conception. In the second part, when I come to the analysis of the concept of acceptance, I will consider an alternative way of unterstanding beliefs, in contrast to other kinds of mental attitudes.

    Google Scholar 

  12. One could point out a number of problematic aspects concerning this factual function of reason. First of all, the interpretation according to which the relation between an individual’s psychological states and its behaviour is of a causal nature is not unanimously accepted. Secondly, one can deny the existence of psychological entities and explain action directly on the basis of processes in the brain. These are points, however, that cannot be discussed in the confines of the present investigation.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf., e. g., Edgley, Roy, Reason in Theory and Practice, London: Hutchinson University Library 1969; also Nagel, Thomas, The Possibility of Altruism, Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  14. This is the opinion, e. g., of Fmnkena, William K., Obligation and Motivation in Recent Moral Philosophy, in: A. I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy, Seattle, Wash.: University of Washington Press 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. Klimovsky, Gregorio, EI método hipotético-deductivo y la Itigica, in: Jorge J. E. Gracia et al. (eds.), Anâlisis Filostifico en América Latina, Mexico-City: Fondo de Cultura Econômica 1985, pp. 75–90.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Redondo, C. (1999). Presentation. In: Reasons for Action and the Law. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 43. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9141-6_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9141-6_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5301-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-9141-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics