Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 269))

Abstract

As we have concluded at the end of the section 1.7, if we interpret classical quantifiers, individual constants, and generalised quantifiers of any known kinds as subsets of P(D), then the semantically unexploited subsets of this set can still remain. Let us assume then that they can serve as interpretations of the extended (beyond quantifiers and constants) term category. Now suppose, for example, that t is a term such that I(t) = {set of idlers, set of students}. Then it turns out that t (or, more precisely, the entity represented by t) possesses, in the sense determined by the truth condition (2) in 1.6, the following properties: being lazy, being a student, being a human, etc. At the same time, it does not possess many other properties, like being a cat, being a girl, being handsome, being not handsome, etc. So t may be identified as lazy student (we do not put here any article since neither does justice to the meaning of the term). In a similar way we may create more objects, and even, in a sense, every thinkable and nameable object, and this procedure will perfectly agree with the bundle theory of objects. If we once admit that an individual may be represented by (or even identified with) a set of properties, why not allow every set of properties to represent an object?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. We can define the set of formulas in a simpler way by replacing conditions (c) and (d) with a single condition: if A is a formula then txA is a formula. However, it is important for us to mention the predicate category explicitly.

    Google Scholar 

  2. To introduce the existential quantifier “officially” we should consider it as a primitive term of M-language and, additionally, adopt the following additional axiom: -VxAD3x-A (the reverse implication, as we shall see, follows from the axioms: thesis M11).

    Google Scholar 

  3. We adopt several conventions which will be frequently used in proofs or in descriptions of proofs in order to make them more clear: (a) derived rules will be designated by respective axioms or theses; (b) numbers in parentheses will indicate numbers of proof lines to which the respective rules were applied; however, there will be no number if those were applied to the line immediately preceding the current one; (c) derivations based on the sentential calculus, truth functional derivations, will be indicated by Ml or will not be indicated at all; (d) we will not mention the use of very common rules just giving the number of line to which they were applied; (e) in order to further to shorten proofs we will use compound derivations, if e.g. FADB then according to MG-M2 we get txADtxB. In the case where the order of the application of rules is unimportant, we will use a comma rather than a dash; (f) when nothing follows a thesis it means that the proof is trivial; sometimes we mention only numbers of theses from which the proof immediately follows. The use of these conventions will be flexible, adjusted to formal complexity of a given proof.

    Google Scholar 

  4. To see how far the duality enables us to shorten proofs, we present the proof of M9 not appealing to this property of M-system:

    Google Scholar 

  5. See our discussion of monotonicity in the previous chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  6. I.e. for any set XcP(D), the maximal set is X={YcD: 3Z,XZcY}. It should be noticed that the minimal set with respect to the relation = does not alwayes exist. E.g. assume that D=N (the set of natural nukmbers) and consider the following subset of P(D): (XcD: V„, N X={n,n+1,...}}.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Although M„-formulas coincide with M-formulas we write “M„-formulas” to indicate their narrower interpretation.

    Google Scholar 

  8. In particular, the following M-formulas are theses of M*-logic: The formulas can be understood as saying that if a term t is not an individual constant (for individual constants we have: tx - A = - txA) then the term either coincides with or with `d, i.e. it is not distinguishable from the quantifiers with respect to predication (recall that the reverse implcations: txBDxB and VxBDtxB are theses of M-system).

    Google Scholar 

  9. We still mention here “∃” as merely an abbreviation of” -Vx n“. Instead of ”∃ we may put any other term but this one seems to be the most natural.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Since B does not contain any free variable besides x,we do not relativise I to an assignment.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Notice that generally Ct)[xBJ* - (t[xB]) and 3[xB]=3 for every xB such that 1(xB)D.

    Google Scholar 

  12. They will coincide with the classical restricted quantifiers on the ground of the free M-logic, see section 4.1.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Notice that as far as y#B then [xB] and [yB(y |x)] are indistinguishable in the sense of M5.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. da Costa, Doria, Papavero [ 1991 ].

    Google Scholar 

  15. Actually tx(B1,,B n ) is a more general syntactic and semantic notion of definite description than the Russellian one. Notice that only one formula can define the Russelian description whereas the description in M-logic is defined by a sequence of formulas and tx(B1,,B n ) does not coincide with tx(B,A…AB„).

    Google Scholar 

  16. When This description is introduced to the free version of M-logic then the case when existence or uniqueness is lacking is the same as in the standard theory of description, i.e. all predications turn out to be false. See section 4.1.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Also, if DM2 is already present in M*-logic then the logic can dispense with one of its specific axioms: M*1 or M*2 since the two axioms, as one can easily notice, are dual one to another.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Paśniczek, J. (1998). M-Logic. In: The Logic of Intentional Objects. Synthese Library, vol 269. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8996-3_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8996-3_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4968-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8996-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics