Skip to main content

The Two Scepticisms of the Savoyard Vicar

  • Chapter
Scepticism in the Enlightenment

Abstract

I have known Dick Popkin since the end of 1966. I was then preparing my Ph.D dissertation about Leibniz’ criticism of Descartes, exploring some issues that were not considered in Yvon Belaval’s famous book about the subject. Both my thesis director — Professor Jose Ferrater Mora (Bryn Mawr College) -and myself? considered that this research program was a natural sequence of my Argentine dissertation “The Methodic ‘Doubt’ and Its Post-Cartesian Criticisms” (Buenos Aires University, 1963). In 1966 Dick had just published “Leibniz and the French Sceptics” in the Revue Internationale de Philosophie, an article that distilled an always sincere although not always fair dislike of Leibniz. In his essay Dick quoted Fabricius’ claim that Leibniz once planned to write a criticism of Sextus Empiricus and yet had not fulfilled his promise. I immediately wrote to Dick pointing out to him that Leibniz had in fact written that polemical work and that it was lying, with many other manuscripts, in his unpublished legacy in Hannover. I thought that my remark was going to alter Dick’s plans and that an analysis of Leibniz’ paper should find its place in future editions of The History of Scepticism. As a matter of fact, I was the one who had to change my plans. Indeed, Dick convinced me that I should decipher Leibniz’ Latin manuscript, and write a commentary about it, and that I should change the subject of my dissertation to Leibniz’ criticism of Sextus Empiricus.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. An earlier version of this paper was read at the Center for Logic. Epistemology, and the History of Science, Campinas State University, Campinas, Brazil. in October 1978. It was published in Spanish in Manusonto. Vol. 3. 1980, pp. 7–23. I am grateful to the editors for permission to use portions of that article.

    Google Scholar 

  2. “Scepticism in the Enlightenment”, Studies on Voltaire and the Eighreenth Century, Vol. 24/27, 1963, pp. 1321–1345.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Giorgio Tonelli, “La question des bornes de l’entendement humain au XVIIIe siϨcle et la genϨse du criticisme kantien”, Revue de Mϩtaphysique et de Morale, Vol. 4, 1959, pp. 396–427; “Die Anfange von Kants Kritik der Kausalbeziehungen und ihre Voraussetzungen im 18. Jahrundert”, Kant-Studien, Vol. 57. 1966, pp. 417–456; “Kant und die antiken Skeptiker” in Studicn zu Kants philosophischer Entwicklung, hrsg. v. H. Heimsoeth, Hildesheim: Olms, 1967. pp. 93–123. “The ‘Weakness’ of Reason in the Age of Enlightenment”, Diderot Studies, Vol. 14, 1971. pp. 217–244. See also infra note 15.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Noc. At. 11. See my essay “On Hume’s Scepticism Again,” Manuscrito, Vol. I, 1978, pp.45–73.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Rousseau Juge de Jean-Jacques. Deuxiϩme Dialogue. in Oeuvres ComplϨtes. Plϩiade edition. Vol. 1. p. S38 (hereafter referred to as ‘OC’). Letter to Mereau. March 1963. in Correspondance Gϩnϩrale. Th. Dufour and Plan. eds., Paris. 192W1934. Vol. 9. pp. 140–141, and Letter to Beaumont. OC. Vol. 4. p. 991. See P. Burgelin. La Philosophie de l’Existence de J.-J. Rousseau. Paris: J.Vrin, 1973. p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Yvon Belaval must be credited with this witticism. See his “Rationalisme sceptique et dogmatisme du sentiment chez Jean-Jacques Rousseau”. Annales de ia Societϩ J.-J. Rousseau. Vol. 38. 1969–1971. pp. 7–21. At the end of the present essay I examine an important thesis offered by Belaval in this article.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Discours de la Methode. 3. in Oeuvres de Descartes. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. eds., Paris: J. Vrin. 1897–1913 (hereafter referred to as ‘AT’). Vol.6. pp. 2S-/9. Diogenes Laertius, Life of Pyrrho, in Lives of Eminent Philosophers. R.D. Hicks, ed., Loeb edition. London: W. Heinemann, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1950. See also Descartes’ Lettre-Preface to Principes de la Philosophie AT, Vol. 9B, p. 6.51

    Google Scholar 

  8. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, trans. by R.G. Bury, London: W. Heinemann, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1933 (hereafter referred to as ‘PH’), p. 7: Sexti Empiric: Opera quae extant . . . Pyrrhoniarum Hypotyposeon libri III... Henrico Stephano interprete .. . etc. Paris, Geneva: P. & J. Chouet, 1621, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. I argue in “The Meaning of Sceptical Doubt” (Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofia Buenos Aires, Vol. 1, 1975, pp. 27–37) that if epochϩ is 2 suspension of dubious (and so of perturbing) -judgments, it is at least confusing to identify doubt and epochϩ.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Emile, Barbara Foxley, tr., London, New York: Everyman’s Library, s.d., p. 23Q. All passages quoted in the text are from this edition unless otherwise indicated. See also Letter to Voltaire, OC, Vol. 4, pp. 1070–1071 and OC, Vol. 1, p. 879.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. 272.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Jean Pierre de Crousaz, Examen du pyrrhonisme. The Hague: publisher unknown, 1733.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See the exposition of the ten modes as a (perhaps Democntean) counterpoint of physis and nomos, PH, pp.59, 78, 87, 93, 100–103, 119, 123, 125, 128, 129, 132, 135, 140, and 163. Except for the ninth mode he appears always in search of physis.

    Google Scholar 

  14. PH, I, 22–24.

    Google Scholar 

  15. I have labeled this attitude “Limitationism”, see supra note 9.

    Google Scholar 

  16. G. Tonelli, “Pierre-Jacques Changeux and Scepticism in the French Enlightenment”, Studia Leibnitiana, Vol. 6, 1974, pp. 106–126; see especially: “But as Locke, in my opinion, was in fact an academic sceptic, French XVIIlth Century Lockeanism, being in most of the cases a kind of scepticism, seems to me to be much more genuine than the British. If Hume as a sceptic did not arouse much interest in France, this may well have happened because the ‘philosophes’ were very well acquainted in advance with many basic traits of Hume’s scepticism, which had been developed within the local tradition, e.g. by Maupertuis”, p. 112. Compare this with Popkin’s claim in “Skepticism and anti-Skepticism in the Latter Part of the Eighteenth Century” in The High Road to Pyrrhonism, San Diego: Austin Hill Press, 1980, pp. 58–59.

    Google Scholar 

  17. P.H. Masson, cited by Burgelin, op. cit., p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Pierre Villey, Les sources et l’ϩvolution des essais de Montaigne. Paris: Hachette, 1908. Richard H. Popkin, The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press, 1979, p. 43 et passim.; The High Road to Pyrrhonism, p. 229.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Notae in programma, AT, Vol. 8, p. 367.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The term “critϨre”, as Bouchardy points out, was diffused by Rousseau; see OC, Vol. 3, p. 1248, OC, Vol. 4, p. 1518, and Gouhier’s remarks OC, Vol. 4, pp. cxci-cxcii.

    Google Scholar 

  21. “I find that the Cartesians are ridiculous because they want to give a reason of every natural effect by means of their assumptions, and I find that the Newtonians are even more ridiculous because they take their assumptions as if they were facts: et us be satisfied with our knowledge of matters of fact without pretending to investigate how things are, because such a knowledge is beyond our means”, Mϩmoire Ϡ Mably, OC, Vol. 4, p. 30. In a footnote Spink considers that “this statement is too Pyrrhonian for 1740”, OC, Vol. 4, p. 1264. footnote 6.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Les mϩditationa mϩtaphysiqus de J.-J. Rousseau. Paris; J. Vrin, 1970, Ch. 2. In the first Part of the Creed. Rousseau’s attacks are directed mainly against the author of the article “Evidence” of the Encyclopϩdie who, according to Rousseau, is either Condillac or Buffon, although nowadays is supposed to be Quesnay; OC, Vol. 4, pp. 1129 and 1304.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Nouvelle Hϩloise, Vol. 6, p. 2; OC, Vol. 2, p. 708. See also ωmile. OC, Vol. 4, p. 1513.

    Google Scholar 

  24. The Vicar is not dogmatic regarding metaphysic, as Rousseau says to Beaumm. He is a sceptic. Already in his letter to Voltaire he “ingeniously” confesses that in respect to God’s existence “the light of reason” show neither its pro nor its con,” and that if the theist bases his feelings on probabilities, the atheist, even less accurate, seems to base his own feelings only on the opposite possibilities. Furthermore, the objections raised by both sides are always unsolvable because they concern matters about which we do not have true ideas” (in manuscript “2” there are the following crossed out words: “such as infinite, eternity, substance, matter, mind, necessity, contingency, and other words that mean nothing to us”). OC, Vol. 4, pp. 1070–1071. See also the important paragraph of Rousseau Juge de Jean Jacques, OC, Vol. 1, p. 879. The conclusion is paradoxical: the best metaphysics is the spiritualist, although it is certainly beyond the reach of human mind and may even be false.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See my essay “Leibniz et l’art de disputer”, Studia Leibnitiana Supplementa, Vol. 5, Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner, 1975, pp. 207–228. Rousseau had this in mind when he wrote his letters to Sophie, the Creed’s first sketch: “I agree that they are only conjectures without probability, but if the opposite cannot be proven then it is enough for me to infer those doubts that I desire to state. Where are we? What do we see, what do we know, what does exist? We are only running after evanescent shadows”, OC, Vol. 4, pp. 1098–1099; see Nouvelle Hϩloise OC, Vol. 2, p. 707; and in the same work: “we don’t assume that we are active and free, we feel it. They have the burden of proving (‘c’est Ϡ eux de prouver’) not only that this feeling could deceive us, but that in fact it does deceive us”, OC, Vol. 2, pp. 683–684.

    Google Scholar 

  26. “Here I have, therefore, abandoned reason and consulted nature, i.e. the inner feeling that guides my belief independently from reason”, Correspondence gϩnϩrale,Vol. 3, p. 287, quoted by P. Burgelin in OC, Vol. 4, p. 1517, footnote 4.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Belaval’s essay quoted supra in note 6. Yet Rousseau’s originality, about which he was completely aware, lies in his refusal to identify moral conscience’s voice and judgment. See Nouvelle Hϩloise, OC, Vol. 6, p. 7; OC, Vol. 2, p. 683.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Letter to Voltaire, OC, Vol. 4, p. 1072.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See supra note 14 and PH, 1, 193.

    Google Scholar 

  30. The acts of conscience would, then, form an autonomous domain, extrinsic to reason. For analysis of the difficulties implied by this thesis for Rousseau’s own doctrine, see Y. Beiaval, “La thϩorie du jugement dans L’ωmile”, in Jean Jacques Rousseau et son oeuvre, Paris: Klincksieck, 1963, p. 154. For some problems concerning the interpretation of this notion of conscience, see L.G. Crocker, Nature and Culture. Ethical Thought in the French Enlightenment, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1963. pp. 171–176.

    Google Scholar 

  31. “Although, following the ordinary life, we affirm undogmatically that Gods exist and reverence Gods and ascribe to them foreknowledge, yet as against the rashness of the Dogmatists we argue as follows . . .” PH, 3, 2. Is not this passage a rough anticipation of the Vicar’s program concerning religion?

    Google Scholar 

  32. As far as I know no one has yet studied the similarities between Rousseau’s and Kant’s style of rejecting classical metaphysics. It has not yet even been remarked either by Cassirer or by later commentators. See Ernst Cassirer’s “Kant and Rousseau” in Rousseau, Kant, Goethe, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1945, pp. 1–60, and S.J. Al Azm’s, The Origins of Kant’s Arguments in the Antinomies, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See my booklet Scepticism and Enlightenment, Valencia: Carabobo University Press, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  34. I wish to express my thanks to Leiser Madanes and Pina Montoreano who helped me translate this essay from Spanish and also for translating some of Rousseau’s texts from French. I also express my thanks to Richard A. Watson for many valuable suggestions concerning the translation into English.

    Google Scholar 

  35. [An earlier version of this paper was read at the Center for Logic. Epistemology, and the History of Science, Campinas State University, Campinas, Brazil. in October 1978. It was published in Spanish in Manuscrito. Vol. 3. 1980, pp. 7–23. I am grateful to the editors for permission to use portions of that article.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

De Olaso, E. (1997). The Two Scepticisms of the Savoyard Vicar. In: Popkin, R.H., De Olaso, E., Tonelli, G. (eds) Scepticism in the Enlightenment. Archives Internationales d’histoire des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 152. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8953-6_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8953-6_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4877-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8953-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics