Skip to main content

Platonic Idealism in Modern Philosophy from Malebranche to Berkeley

  • Chapter
The Cambridge Platonists in Philosophical Context

Abstract

The revival of Platonism associated with Cambridge philosophers such as Henry More and Ralph Cudworth was in part a reaction against Calvinism with its stress on faith rather than reason and its pessimistic view of human nature. It was not, however, the only revival of Platonism in England in the late seventeenth century. There was another more broadly European revival that lasted well into the eighteenth century. This new Platonism was in some respects significantly different, both in its inspiration and in its nature, from that of Henry More and his associates. The Cambridge Platonists largely regarded Descartes and the mechanical philosophy as a challenge and even a threat to religious faith. The new Platonism, by contrast, had its beginnings in a new perspective on Descartes and the mechanical view of nature in which they came to be regarded as actually conducive to piety. This new perspective came to be quite widely shared thanks to the popularity of the writings of Malebranche in whose thought Cartesianism was harmonised with an Augustinian Christian philosophy and theology.

I owe a general debt to the work of André Robinet for a sense of the importance of Malebranche for Leibniz’s philosophy. I am also indebted to Charles McCracken’s Malebranche and British Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983). Sarah Hutton has encouraged me to expect that Platonism continued to flourish in early eighteenth century England more than historians of the philosophy of that period have recognised. I am indebted for the discussion of an earlier draft of the paper at the Nantes Conference on “Le Monde des Platoniciens de Cambridge” in 1993, particularly to the contribution from Roselyne Degremont.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. I owe a general debt to the work of André Robinet for a sense of the importance of Malebranche for Leibniz’s philosophy. I am also indebted to Charles McCracken’s Malebranche and British Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983). Sarah Hutton has encouraged me to expect that Platonism continued to flourish in early eighteenth century England more than historians of the philosophy of that period have recognised. I am indebted for the discussion of an earlier draft of the paper at the Nantes Conference on “Le Monde des Platoniciens de Cambridge” in 1993, particularly to the contribution from Roselyne Degremont.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Clavis Universalis, or, a New Inquiry After Truth being a Demonstration of the Non-Existence, or Impossibility of an External World, (London: Gosling, 1713), ed. E. Bowman, (Chicago: Open Court, 1909), p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  3. “Materia est infima omnium rerum, & prope nihil” (“Matter is the lowest of all things, and strictly speaking, nothing”) (ibid, p. 97).

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Siris 332. The unfashionable Renaissance Platonist sentiment is partially reflected also in the remark that “though, perhaps, it may not be relished by some modern readers, yet the treating in physical books concerning metaphysical and divine matters can be justified by great authorities among the ancients”. (Siris, 297).

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Sect. IV below.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Acts 17: 18. As Stoic philosophers were listed among Paul’s audience the author of Acts of the Apostles may be presumed to have intended the phrase to be taken in a Stoic way. But Berkeley clearly interpreted the phrase in a Platonic way, assuming God to be a pure Spirit. See below, Section IV.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Recherche de la Vérité, III, ii, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The Berkeley citations include Philosophical Commentaries, 827, Principles of Human Knowledge, 66 and 149 and the title page of the Theory of Vision Vindicated. For citations in the Three Dialogues see A. A. Luce and T. E. Jessop (eds), The Works of George Berkeley, Bishop of Cloyne, (Edinburgh: Nelson, 9 vols, 1948–57), Vol. 2, pp. 214 & 236.

    Google Scholar 

  9. In the case of Collier some of the evidence is probably lost, but according to Robert Benson, who had access to the lost manuscripts, this was one of Collier’s “favourite maxims”. (Robert Benson, Memoirs of the Life and Writings of the Reverend Arthur Collier, (London: Lumley, 1837, reprinted Bristol: Thoemmes Antiquarian Books, 1990), pp. 54f.) One citation, from Collier’s Logology of 1832, is quoted by Benson (ibid., p. 76). Collier seems to have interpreted the “Platonic” passages of the Bible in the light of one another and took the early verses of John 1 to mean that God made all things by, through and in the Son. (Clavis, p. 104). He may have used Acts 17: 18 to support his unusual view that the whole creation existed not only by and through but in the Son of God.

    Google Scholar 

  10. This work is in a number ways reminiscent of a book by an English Neoplatonist of the early seventeenth century, Robert Fludd. In that book, called the Mosaicall Philosophy, Fludd had held that the true natural philosophy was to be found in a correct interpretation of the beginning of the Book of Genesis. The idea that Moses was a divinely inspired philosopher was much favoured by Renaissance Neoplatonists who linked Moses with Plato through various legends of which the most famous was that Plato learned his philosophy from the Hebrews. Collier, writing nearly a century later, did not pretend to extract the true science from the Book of Genesis but only the true metaphysics.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Robert Benson, op. cit., p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  12. The term is not without its difficulties and controversies. In a way, too, it is misleading, since pantheists (e.g. Spinoza) also hold that all things are contained in God. It is necessary to make clear that panentheists do not think of this relationship as a part-whole one. Collier, accepting a Scholastic conception of “cause” as containing its effects, would naturally embrace panentheism as a consequence of God being the “first cause”. Thus he wrote that “... before these created minds, there is, or was, an uncreated mind, in which a whole heaven and earth existed, and does exist. ..” (Memoirs, p. 51). Berkeley, for his part, held that everything is contained in the Divine Intellect prior to being created, i.e. made perceptible. Since everything is contained in the Divine Intellect “from all eternity” it continues to be so contained after the Creation. (See Works, VIII 36).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Revelations 3: 14.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Collier, Arthur, A Specimen of True Philosophy: in a Discourse on Genesis, the First Chapter and the First Verse, (Sarum: Horton 1730),

    Google Scholar 

  15. reprinted in Samuel Parr (ed.) Metaphysical Tracts by English Philosophers of the Eighteenth Century, (London: Lumley, 1887), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Op. cit., pp. 13–4.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Assuming, as was generally done without question in this period, that causes are substances. Malebranche did not, however, deny human agency, though he restricted human freedom to a certain control over our thoughts. Leibniz included both Fludd and the occasionalists as among “those who deny a true and proper activity to created things”, (op. cit., Vol. IV, p. 509).

    Google Scholar 

  18. (Leibniz, ed. C. I. Gerhardt, Die Philo sophischen Schriften von G. W. Leibniz, (Berlin, 7 vols, 1875–90), reprinted Hildesheim and New York: Olms 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Recherche de la vérité, III. 2.6. in Œuvres complètes de Malebranche, (Paris: Vrin, 1958–67), Vol. 1, p. 439.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bayle wrote in his famous article on Zeno: “Il est utile de savoir qu’un père de l’oratoire, aussi illustre par sa pieté que par ses lumières philosophiques, a soutenu que la foi nous convaine légitemement de l’existence des corps. La Sorbonne, ni aucun autre tribunal, ne lui a point fait d’affaires à cette occasion. Les inquisiteurs d’Italie n’en point fait à M. Fardella, qui a soutenu la même chose dans un ouvrage imprimé. Cela doit apprendre à mes lecteurs qu’il ne faut pas qu’ils trouvent étrange que je fasse voir quelquefois que sur les matières les plus mystérieuses de l’Évangile, la raison nous met à bout; et qu’alors nous devons nous contenter pleinement des lumières de la foi.” Dictionnaire historique et critique, (ed. 1820–24 Paris), Vol. XV, p. 52. (Reprinted Geneva: Slatkine, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Locke, John, An Examination of Pere Malebranche’s Opinion of Seeing All Things in God, Sect. 20, first published in King, P. (ed. 1706) Posthumous Works of Mr. John Locke, London, 1706.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Collier claims that to remove an external world is to quench the “very vital flame” of the “doctrine of transubstantiation”. (Clavis, p. 126) Berkeley makes a more oblique reference in Principles, section 124, where he claims that it would be impossible for the abstract idea of an infinitely invisible extension to gain the assent of any reasonable creature if “he was not brought to it by gentle and slow degrees, as a pagan convert to the belief of transubstantiation”.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Walter Graham, (ed.) Letters of Joseph Addison, (Oxford: OUP, 1941), p. 25, quoted in McCracken, Malebranche and British Philosophy, p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Addison’s oration Nova philosophia veter proeferenda est was not published until after his death. His tendency to a Modern Platonism seems to have been initially the influence of his teacher at the Charterhouse, Thomas Burnet, in whose honour he wrote a Platonic poem. His letter on Malebranche was addressed to John Hough, formerly President of Magdalen and perhaps himself a supporter of the new philosophy. The third orator was Richard Smallbroke, who himself became a Bishop of Lichfield.

    Google Scholar 

  25. One of Norris’s correspondents, Elizabeth Thomas, learnt French specially to be able to read Malebranche in the original. She defended his views about the love of God against the Lockean Richard Gwinnett. See Pylades and Corinna or, Memoirs of the lives amours, and writings of Richard Gwinett....and Elizabeth Thomas, (London, 1731), Volume 2, pp. 31–2.

    Google Scholar 

  26. André Robinet, Malebranche et Leibniz, (Paris: Vrin, 1955). See my Leibniz, (Brighton: Harvester Press, 1984), Ch. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See also my introduction to R. N. D. Martin and Stuart Brown, (eds) G. W. Leibniz: Discourse on Metaphysics and Related Writings, (Manchester: University Press, 1988

    Google Scholar 

  28. “Malebranche’s Occasionalism and Leibniz’s Pre-established Harmony: an ‘Easy Crossing’ or an Unbridgeable Gap?” in Stuart Brown, (ed.) Nicolas Malebranche: His Philosophical Critics and Successors, (Assen/Maastricht: Van Gorcum, 1991), pp. 81–93.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Leibniz, Philosophische Schriften, Vol. IV, p.337.

    Google Scholar 

  30. “Cartesium attulisse aliqua egregia negari non potest, et recte inprimis Platonis studium revocasse abducendi mentem a sensibus, et Academicas dubitationes utiliter subinde adhibuisse ...”Op. cit., Vol. IV, p. 468.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Leibniz, ed. Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften, Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, (Darmstadt and Leipzig; Akademie-Verlag, 1923—), Series VI, Vol. vi, pp. 47 and 70.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Leibniz, Philosophische Schriften, Vol. III, p. 568.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Op. cit., Vol. III, p. 637.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Op. cit., Vol. III, p. 659.

    Google Scholar 

  35. “Platonici posteriores ad loquendi portenta sunt lapsi; Aristotelicis, praesertim Scholasticis, movere magis questiones curae fuit, quam finire.” Op. cit., Vol. IV, p. 468.

    Google Scholar 

  36. “Ficinus et Patritius ont ensuivi Platon, mais mal à mon avis, parce qu’ils se sont jettés sur les pensées hyperboliques, et ont abandonné ce qui estoit plus simple et en même temps plus solide. Ficinus ne parle partout que d’idées, d’Ames du monde, de Nombres Mystiques et choses semblables, au lieu de poursuivre les exactes definitions, que Platon tache de donner des notions. Je souhaitterois que quelqu’un tirât des anciens le plus propre à l’usage et le plus conforme au goust de nostre siecle ...”. Op. cit., Vol. I, p. 380.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Russell, in his Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz, (London: Allen and Unwin, 1900), accused Leibniz of being committed to both pantheism and determinism and of being much closer to Spinoza in his metaphysics than he cared to acknowledge.

    Google Scholar 

  38. “ ... à quoi peut servir tout ce grand artifice dans les substances, si non pour faire croire que les unes agissent sur les autres, quoique cela ne soit pas? En vérité, il me semble que ce système n’est guères plus avantageux que celui des Cartésiens; et si on a raison de rejetter le leur, parce qu’il suppose inutilement que Dieu considérent les mouvements qu’il produit lui-même dans le corps, produit aussi dans l’âme des pensées qui correspondent a ces movemens; comme s’il n’étoit pas plus digne que lui de produire tout d’un coup les pensées et les modifications de l’âme, sans qu’il y ait des corps qui lui servent comme de règle, et pour ainsi dire, lui aprennent ce qu’il doit faire; n’aura-t-on pas sujet de vous demander pourquoi Dieu ne se contente point de produire toutes les pensées et modifications de l’ame, soit qu’il le fasse immédiatement ou par artifice, comme vous voudriez, sans qu’il y ait des corps inutiles que 1”esprit ne sçauroit ni remuer ni connoistre?” (Leibniz, Philosophische Schriften, Vol. IV), p. 489.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Op. cit., Vol. IV, p. 495.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Op. cit., Vol. IV, p. 560.

    Google Scholar 

  41. John Norris, A Theory towards the Ideal or Intelligible World, (London: Manship, 1701) Vol. I, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Op. cit., Vol. I, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Op. cit., Vol. I, p. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Op. cit., Vol. I, p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Op. cit., Vol. I, p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  46. According to Benson, Collier Memoirs, p. 18. Some confirmation is provided by the “Credo” of July 14, 1709 in which Collier affirms that God is the efficient, formal, material and final cause of all things. He goes on to explain: “As material cause, etc., I mean the will that created is the very substantial matter of their being; in other words, that particulars, as such, have no distinct substances of their own, but only different forms of similitudes to the one true substance, which one substance is the common substratum to all particulars, which, as such, are creatures”. (Memoirs, p. 192). That doctrine excludes the possibility that matter is the substratum of physical things and seems to be directed against the scholastic notion of matter.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Partly for reasons of space I shall not attempt to bring this out in detail here. Nor can I hope to review the not inconsiderable literature on this topic. But in any case I believe the presumption of plagiarism is based on a mistake and there is no need to undertake to prove that Collier did not benefit from reading Berkeley’s Principles. It is sufficient to show, as I attempt to do, how their philosophies could have converged to the extent that they did.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Collier’s claim, in his Specimen of True Philosophy, that Berkeley”s Dialogues was the only other work that put forward views like his show him, if true, to be ill-read. He seems to have regarded discussion and correspondence as a good way to progress philosophy (Clavis, p. 123) and not to have been concerned with learning in the traditional manner.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Clavis, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Memoirs, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Op. cit., p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Acts of the Apostles, xvii, 29. See above, Notes 7–8.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Op. cit., p. 40. He later abuses his “Aristotelian reader” by saying that his (Aristotelian) studies have made him “long unqualified to receive or apprehend pure unbodied truths”. (op. cit., p. 130).

    Google Scholar 

  54. Clavis, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Op. cit., p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Op. cit., p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Philosophical Commentaries, 290.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Principles, Section 92.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Philosophical Commentaries, 625

    Google Scholar 

  60. Collier’s purpose is not to attack scepticism, but he is anxious to defend himself against the charge of scepticism which it could be Norris made against him personally and which is represented as if it were an objection coming from Norris (Clavis, pp. 110ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Collier, by contrast, regards it as a variation on a familiar (Augustinian) doctrine: “Everyone, I suppose, has heard of the doctrine of seeing the divine ideas, or (as Mr Malebranche expresses it), seeing all things in God”. (Clavis, p. 38f.).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Principles, Sect. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Clavis, p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Op. cit., p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Berkeley does consider the objections that his teachings are contrary to the Bible but denies this, “I do not think, that either what philosophers call matter, or the existence of objects without the mind is any where mention”d in Scripture”. (Principles, Sect. 812).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Works, VIII 36.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Siris, 263.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Siris, 266.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Even if Berkeley was exaggerating his own Platonism, forgetting that on some matters (e.g. his account of mathematics) he had taken a view quite opposed to Platonism throughout his works.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Transcribed by Willy Kabitz in “Leibniz und Berkeley”, Sitzungsberichte der König Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1932, p. 635. The passage is translated in full in Brown, Leibniz, pp. 42–3 and 48.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Norris’s lack of debt to More’s philosophy is argued for in Acworth, Richard, The Philosophy of John Norris of Bemerton (1657–1712), (Hildesheim: Olms, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  72. On Leibniz’s reception of More’s thought see my “Leibniz and More’s Cabbalistic Circle” in Sarah Hutton, (ed.) Henry More (1614–1687) Tercentenary Studies, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1990), pp. 77–95.

    Google Scholar 

  73. As is claimed by Catherine Wilson in her Leibniz’s Metaphysics (Manchester: University Press 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ralph Cudworth, T.I.S.U., I 3 xxxvii, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Op. cit., p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Leibniz, Philosophische Schriften, VI 544.

    Google Scholar 

  77. C.S.P.W., quoted in Ernst Cassirer, trans. J. P. Pettigrove, The Platonic Renaissance in England, (Cambridge University Press, 1950), p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  78. “Moral and Religious Aphorisms”, No. 129, quoted from C. A. Patrides, (ed.) The Cambridge Platonists, (London: Edward Arnold, 1969), p. 328.

    Google Scholar 

  79. T.E.I.M., I ii 3, p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  80. See, for instance, Descartes’ Reply to the Objections of Mersenne, Œuvres de Descartes, (eds. C. Adam and P. Tannery) (Paris: Vrin, 12 vols. 1964–76), IX A 432. See Leibniz’s Discours de Métaphysique, Sect. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  81. I have enlarged on this topic in “The Regularization of Providence in post-Cartesian Philosophy”, in Robert Crocker, (ed.), Religion, Reason and Nature in Early Modern Europe, (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  82. Discours de métaphysique, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Norris, A Theory towards the Ideal in Intelligible World, Vol. I, p. 314.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Discours de métaphysique, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Principles, Section 108.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Siris, 252.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brown, S. (1997). Platonic Idealism in Modern Philosophy from Malebranche to Berkeley. In: Rogers, G.A.J., Vienne, J.M., Zarka, Y.C. (eds) The Cambridge Platonists in Philosophical Context. International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Idées, vol 150. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8933-8_14

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8933-8_14

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4844-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8933-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics