Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 29))

  • 137 Accesses

Abstract

Before throwing ourselves into the gap to explore in more detail Galileo’s idea of motion and its operatic compossibles, we need to take a deep breath and take stock of where we have arrived around the bend.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See below, pp. 163f., 183.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Obviously this distinction presupposes the distinction between mimetic and non- mimetic or indicational appresentation. The distinctions are not quite the same as the antique distinction between Phantasia and Mimesis. See Janson, op. cit., loc. cit., pp. 258f, 265f. See below, pp. 176f.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Galileo Galilei, Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems—Ptolemaic & Copernican , p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., p. 17. See above, pp. 24f.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Galileo, ibid.., pp. 56f.; cf. Descartes, The Meditations Concerning First Philosophy, pp. 75f. Cf. also Jean Dietz Moss, Novelties in the Heavens, pp. 273ff. From what has been said so far, it is obvious that much more than an “architectual metaphor” (p. 275) is involved here.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Galileo, ibid.., p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See above, p.10.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Galileo, Dialogue, pp. 389f. And by also describing the orbit of the earth in the plane of the ecliptic, Salviati even relates the earth seen from the standpoint of the moon to the skies seen from the standpoint of the earth, ibid., p. 390.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Galileo, Dialogue, pp. 7, 416.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Leclerc, op. cit. , pp. 414ff.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Maniates, p. 466. It is a difference which “stems from the incontrovertible fact that early operas still manifest an interest in la meriviglia, ohimé, degli intermedi.” The chief reason for the difference would seem to be the fact that the central focus of early opera is on narrative and lyrical recitative and the mannerist devices for involving the listener in the “lyric core” of the narrative by means of affective appresentation. See also Bukofzer, pp. 394ff. and the discussion of the different kinds of opera (likewise Maniates, p. 467) and the sorts of theatres required. For the essential elements of “meriviglia” in connection with the invention of the theatre, see Celletti, A History of Bel Canto, pp. 20ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Maniates, p. 465. Supposedly the first Italian Renaissance theatre to use the proscenium was the Teatro Farneses at Parma, but I seem unable to confirm this piece of “incidental intelligence.” See also Hammond, Music & Spectacle, pp. 186f.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Drummond, op. cit. , pp. 144ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Celletti, pp. 20f.; Bukofzer, pp. 393ff.; and LeClerc, pp. 419ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Dialogo sopra i due massimi sistemi del mondo, Opere, VII, p. 281 (Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief Systems, p. 256). The translation has been altered slightly to make it more literal.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See above, pp.151f..; below, pp. 173f.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See above, pp. 37ff. For what follows, see also Finocchiaro’s summary and commentary on the arguments about motion in the second day of the Dialogo, pp. 36ff., 54f. See Galileo, Opere, VIII, pp. 184ff. (English translation, pp. 156ff).

    Google Scholar 

  18. See above, pp.108f. and 149f.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Stillman Drake, “Mathematics, Astronomy, and Physic in the Work of Galileo,” pp. 311 ff. Drake does not seem to realize the nature of the composite hypothesis here; see below, pp. 164f., and above, 111 f.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Fred Kersten, “The Life Concept and Life Conviction,” pp. 109–115.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See above, pp. 89f.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Hall, The Revolution in Science , p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Above, pp.143ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Above, p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See Hall, op. cit., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Hall, p. 103. It then comes as no surprise that “To the extent that Galileo’s subject was always the description of motions (kinematics) rather than the action of forces in producing motion (dynamics) he never quite renounced this limitation…”

    Google Scholar 

  27. Hall, op. cit., loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Our formula shows how change in space and time is related in the case of free fall, describing how freely falling bodies behave. In other words, the laws which are constructed must always be of the sort where one aspect, we may say, is a function of another aspect. Thus in our example a functional relationship is established between time and space: S = F(t). What is important here is that there is no cause or effect involved because they have “disappeared” with the introduction of functional dependency. The functional relationship expressed by the formula, F(s, t) = O, effectively eliminates cause and effect, rendering irrelevant the very experiential datum of ordinary life from which it is extrapolated: push coming to shove. To be sure, not to eliminate cause and effect as an icastic image would mean that, for instance, a change in time causes a change in place. And this would, in turn, introduce a productive force into the picture, such as is found in the Aristotelian physics where the paradigm of the occurrence of natural events is the craftsman exerting an effort to bring about a change in the material worked upon in accord with a pre-established form and telos. Now, for Galileo, force, the “power of things,” is conceived as the function of alteration of motion. The datum of extrapolation, push coming to shove, is then a fantastic image. For us, at the moment, the significance of the “how” is that, of necessity, the experiential datum of daily life from which it is extrapolated must be rendered irrelevant so that “reality itself”’ can be rendered. Grateful thanks to Andrew Kersten for help on this footnote.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Hall, op. cit., pp. 102ff. for the description of the advance in Galileo’s description of motion from Treatise on the Sphere to the Discourses.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See above, pp. 111 f..

    Google Scholar 

  31. It was a further step to assume, as Husserl and others have insisted, that this is the only genuine case of idealization, hence of objectivity. Everything else is then “subjective” because it is a non-idealization. This represents a further chapter in the history of modern thought which we cannot pursue here.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See above, pp. 40f.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Above, pp. 43f. For the “fate” of exponential representation, see Paul Schrecker, “On the Infinite Number of Infinite Orders,” pp. 361–373, especially pp. 363ff.

    Google Scholar 

  34. So the Latin epigram, Dialogo, p. 280: Ex hac itaque opinione necesse est diffidere nostris sensibus, ut penitus fallacibus vel stupidis in sensibilibus, etiam coniunctissimis, diiudicandis; quam ergo veritatem sperare possumus, a facultate adeo fallaci ortum trahentem? (Dialogue , p. 255f. “And from this opinion we must necessarily suspect our own senses as wholly fallible or stupid in judging sensible things which are very close at hand. Then what truth can we hope for, deriving its origin from so deceptive a faculty?”); for this notion of “sensory evidence,” see above, pp. 105f., 135f.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., p. 281 (p. 256).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Above, pp.103f.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Finocchiaro, op. cit., Chapter 3, lists and summarizes these and many other “rhetorical” —i.e., fantastic and comic—images, establishing their function in specific arguments in the text of the Dialogo. To be sure, he is concerned with assessing, finally, the “rhetorical force” of the images, even though they may be “pleasing and clever aesthetic” images in their own right. See also Moss, pp. 283ff.

    Google Scholar 

  38. See above, pp.61f., 113f. For the notion of “reason” and its intervention, see above, pp. 104f..

    Google Scholar 

  39. Above, pp. 105f., 113f., 137f.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See Walker, Chapter V, pp. 63ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. See Plessner, Laughing and Crying , pp. 126, 128. This, again, is not obvious, i.e., whether the feelings are genuine or merely sentimental. The whole issue requires a separate inquiry into the criteria of “genuine” as opposed to “sentimental” feelings, and, in turn, of correct or incorrect verisimiltude. Plessner’s view is that “genuine” feelings are those bound to situations, i.e., serious action at the center, and not just objects. The “cultural” difference in “genuine” feelings, i.e., relative to a time or a place, is a different issue; see above, pp. 91f.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Walker, op. cit. , p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Above, pp. 73 f…

    Google Scholar 

  44. See above, pp. 91 f.. Such self-conscious exercise is certainly peculiar to the Baroque; for example, see Walker, pp. 76ff. for a case of “hardness and harshness” in a song of Vincenzo Galilei composed just to express hardness and harshness (reproduced, p. 77) and which contains “only 53 chords, mostly major, which, to my ear, give no impression of hardness or harshness, but produced the effect of a calm, solemn, rather mysterious hymn” (p. 77)—in other words, a case of self-conscious exercise of self-interpretations at odds with “ears” of a later century. Indeed, the self-interpretations are so at odds that one has to ask to “what extent are they a priori constructions, or, on the contrary, derived by induction from the practice of great composers?” (p. 76). Walker admits there is no easy answer; one may add that perhaps the self-interpretations are generically incompatible.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid. , p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Walker, p. 64. Likewise the major third likes to ascend because it is of a “lively and happy nature;” or a minor tenth is weak because it likes to descend, and the major tenth rises because it is lively. See also Lippman, pp. 28f.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Above, pp. 161f..

    Google Scholar 

  48. Walker, p. 65; examples on p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See above, pp. 86f., and Walker, pp. 66ff.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Walker, pp. 67f.; cf. also the discussion of Beeckman by Cohen, pp. 132f.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See above, p70.

    Google Scholar 

  52. See above, pp.161f.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Walker, p. 69; see below, pp.198f.

    Google Scholar 

  54. See ibid., pp. 69f.; also Cohen’s discussion of Galileo’s account of the “physiological” foundations of this indicational appresentation in the Dialogo, pp. 90ff.; and above, pp. 128f.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Walker, pp. 71ff., Cohen, pp. 91ff. (and especially the reference to the studies of Costabel and Lerner which he cites), pp. 168ff. in connection with Descartes. Moreover, the appresented emotions are not themselves always without ambiguity, as is the impression from Peter Kivy’s valuable study, Osmin’s Rage. Philosophical Reflections on Opera, Drama, and Text, pp. 216ff., perhaps leaning too heavily on the “Cartesian” compartmentalization of emotions and the “possible sequence of emotions in the human experience: that being determined, in the present instance, by the Cartesian view” (p. 217); see Walker’s contrast of major and minor modes in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries with those in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, and Cohen pp. 169f. (Perhaps the major disagreement I have with Kivy is his reliance on a “psychology of association” to clarify the theory of affections, and although this is of central importance, especially as concerns the Enlightenment and the use made of it in discussing the da capo form in Chapters IX and X, it misses the non-mimetic nature of appresentation of emotions even in Descartes’ Compendium musicae. That is to say, the “association” is the result of appresentation by way of opposites, i.e., the Cartesian principle of truth by least resemblance, above, pp. 104f., 135f.—and which is entailed by Kivy’s important distinction between the Baroque and contemporary interpretation of expressiveness where, on the former, music “arouses” emotions, and on the latter music possesses emotive qualities. See Kivy’s discussion of Archibald Alison, pp. 207ff.)

    Google Scholar 

  56. See above, pp. 145f.; for what follows, see Claudio Monteverdi, Orfeo; Maniates, Mannerism in Italian Music and Culture, pp. 472ff.; Kivy, Osmin’s Rage, Chapter V. For the performance of Orfeo, I prefer, for the most part, that of Nikolaus Harnoncourt and Jean-Pierre Ponnelle in 1978 at the Zurich Opera House (London: CD Video 071 203–1).

    Google Scholar 

  57. Iain Fenlon, in Whenham, op. cit., pp. 16f. As Monteverdi himself notes in dedicatory preface to first printed edition of 1609, L’Orfeo was given in the large, 4000-seat Manutuan theatre as well.

    Google Scholar 

  58. See Kivy, op. cit., pp. 73ff.; Silke Leopold, Monteverdi. Music in Transition, pp. 86ff.

    Google Scholar 

  59. See Whenham, op. cit.., p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  60. See Leopold, pp.91f.; Hanning, Of Poetry and Music ’s Power, pp. 118ff.

    Google Scholar 

  61. See Maniates’ careful account of e.g., “Possente spirto” op. cit.., note 55, pp. 561f. and Kivy, op. cit., ibid..; Leopold, pp. 60, 89, 92f.

    Google Scholar 

  62. See above, pp. 96f.. and Manitates’ references to Guarini, op. cit.., pp. 472f.

    Google Scholar 

  63. See Maniates, p. 472. To be sure, in a few decades this and similar terms will disappear.

    Google Scholar 

  64. See Leopold, p. 85, and the citations there from Doni’s Tratto della musica scenica; also Maniates, op. cit., ibid.. For Doni, see also Lippman, pp. 42ff.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Kivy wrestles these to the ground in op. cit., Chapter V, centered around the question ultimately of just what sort of work, musical or dramatic, Orfeo is; see especially pp. 91ff.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Maniates, ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ibid., and pp. 510ff. In contrast, see Drummond, pp. 122, 135.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Palisca, Humanism in Italian Renaissance Musical Thought, p. 432.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See Celletti, op. cit., pp. 4ff.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Thus the issue of whether the stile rappresentativo is in one or some other sense “melody” is hardly important; at the least, melody rides in on the back of the stile rappresentativo regardless of whether it itself is “melodic.” See Kivy, op. cit., pp. 90f.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Leopold, op. cit.., p. 85. Maniates as well, pp. 475f. notes the strictures of Doni followed not only by Monteverdi but Peri, Rinuccini, and others as well: “We should not imagine that the shepherds depicted there were the sordid and common ones that tend the livestock today, but those of that older age when the noblest people practised this art” (Cited by Leopold, p. 85)—another case of “what seems right” in Arcadia rather than in Thrace. See also Thomas G. Rosenmeyer, The Green Cabinet. Theocritus and the European Pastoral Lyric, pp. 232ff., especially p. 235.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Harnoncourt, The Musical Dialogue, pp. 127f.

    Google Scholar 

  73. See above, pp. 113, 149f..

    Google Scholar 

  74. See above, pp. 128ff.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Maniates, p. 475. To be sure, it will not be long before Arcadia becomes the playground of the comic and ridiculous, as e.g.,in Monteverdi’s next Manutuan opera, La finta pazza l icori: “the pastoral world, which had dominated the first stage of operatic history, came to an end with the new dramas dealing with thrilling entanglements and intrigues. Only a little later stingy nymphs, sly shepherds, and vulgar gods will appear. A Narcissus who wastes away from loving his own reflection, an Echo who turns to stone because of the sorrow of love, were truly no longer part of the world.” Arcadia is “reduced to an arbitrary, interchangeable background.”(Leopold, p. 103.) That is to say, the arcadian room-milieu is indifferent to the comic or the tragic, and indifferently can be either.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Leopold, p. 85; see above, p. 155f.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Above, pp.5f..

    Google Scholar 

  78. Below, p 179.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Above, pp.69, 130f., 141f…

    Google Scholar 

  80. See above, p. 134; see Plessner, Laughing and Crying, p. 152: “What is common to laughing and crying is that they are answers to a boundary situation. Their opposition depends on the mutually contrasted directions in which man falls into this boundary situation. Since it makes itself known as a boundary situation only in the twofold way in which every possible mode of human behavior is blocked or thwarted, there are only two crisis reactions having the character of a response to such a situation. Laughter responds to the thwarting of behavior by the irremediable ambiguity of cues to action, crying to the thwarting of behavior by the negation of the relativity of human existence.” In the specious present of the fable, however, there is an ambiguity affirmed at the end of the opera as well (not in the libretto) when Orpheus and Eurydice are united in the stars. There is an ambiguous zone between laughing and crying that remains; it is a case of laughing and crying at the same time, just as with the kiss and the bite. This ambiguity of the kiss would seem to be especially Marinist in character; cf. Monteverdi’s setting, in the Seventh Book of Madrigals of 1619, of Marino’s “Tornate, o cari baci” and “Vorrei baciarti;” see Tomlinson, Monteverdi, pp. 185ff., and Leopold, Monteverdi, pp. 64f.

    Google Scholar 

  81. See below, pp. 209f..; for the difference in Act V of Orfeo see Leopold, pp. 94f.; Maniates, pp. 472f.; Sternfeld, pp. 29ff.; Drummond, p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  82. See above, pp. 131f.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Leopold, p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Ibid. , p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Leopold, p. 97; Maniates, pp. 561f.; Harnoncourt, pp. 126ff.

    Google Scholar 

  86. See above, pp.90f.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Above, pp.98f.

    Google Scholar 

  88. See Leopold, p. 97, for the significance of the lyre in the central scenes of Orpheus and the precedence for in the Mantuan song tradition that includes Poliziano’s Fabula d’Orfeo. See also Celletti, Voce di Tenore, pp. 24ff.

    Google Scholar 

  89. See above, pp.101 f.

    Google Scholar 

  90. See above, pp. 96f. Celletti, A History of Bel Canto, pp. 26f.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Tomlinson, p. 237. In the preceding pages Tomlinson makes a strong case for his “archeologies” over against other approaches.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Musical Quarterly, pp. 346–359.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Tomlinson, p. 240.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Ibid., pp. 240f.

    Google Scholar 

  95. We have already referred in this connection to the practice of the ostinato or ground p g bass above, pp.88f., 105..

    Google Scholar 

  96. Thus we are far removed from Lawrence Ferrara’s Philosophy and the Analysis of Music, or Bruce Bensen’s “Improvising Music: An Essay on Musical Hermeneutics.”

    Google Scholar 

  97. In Angelo Solerti, Le Origini del Melodrama (Torino: Fratelli Bocca, 1903), pp. 57ff. See also Lippman, op. cit., pp. 37ff.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Traced in Leopold, Chapter 3, pp. 104ff.

    Google Scholar 

  99. See Palisca, op. cit.., pp. 431ff.; Leopold, pp. 106ff.

    Google Scholar 

  100. See Harnoncourt, The Musical Dialogue, pp. 29ff., who insists that the “freedom” to declaim lies in a distinction we have to make between the work itself and the performance. See below, pp. 209f.

    Google Scholar 

  101. palisca, p. 432.

    Google Scholar 

  102. For this distinction, see Celletti, A History of Bel Canto, pp. 7, 15, 26, 32f.

    Google Scholar 

  103. See Leopold, pp. 108f.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Ibid., p. 114. But see Harnoncourt, pp. 30f.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Ibid., p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  106. See Harnoncourt, pp. 129f., who discusses the ways in which “the same bass was harmonized differently”—different harmonic solutions even when the “same voices are supplied” and, we may add, just as the vanishing point can be different for the same scene depicted in a painting with a correlative change in the grid or veil.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Ibid., p. 119. See below, pp.162. Perhaps it would be easier to visualize— “auralize”?—this situation if one has in mind “What child this is” of Greensleves, which is built over a descending tetrachord yielding its own peculiar harmonies.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Ibid., p. 120.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Tomlinson, pp. 207ff. provides a remarkably succinct and fascinating account of Il cannocchiale aristotelico of Tesauro. Cf. also Maniates, pp. 26ff. on Tesauro and Gracián; and Hauser, Mannerism, pp. 297ff. See also Tomlinson, Monteverdi, pp. 223ff.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Tomlinson, pp. 211. The icastic images belong to the “plain, grammatical, proper, and dialectical manner,” the fantastic to the “rhetorical, poetic and figurative manner” (p. 210).

    Google Scholar 

  111. Ibid., p. 211; see p. 242.

    Google Scholar 

  112. See Hauser, p. 298.

    Google Scholar 

  113. See above, p167.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Cf. Plessner, p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  115. See below, pp. 196f.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Above, pp.93, 102.

    Google Scholar 

  117. For a discussion of the problems inherent in the discussion of truth and verisimilitude, see A. J. Ayer, “Truth, Verification and Versimilitude,” pp. 684–692.

    Google Scholar 

  118. See Whenham, op. cit., pp. 39ff.

    Google Scholar 

  119. See above, pp.133.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Above, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kersten, F. (1997). Life at the Gap. In: Galileo and the ‘Invention’ of Opera. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 29. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8931-4_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8931-4_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4847-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8931-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics