Skip to main content

Eloquence is Power: The Office of Rhetoric

  • Chapter
  • 132 Accesses

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 262))

Abstract

The substantial question of Hobbes’s rhetoric immediately splits into two: Hobbes’s use of rhetoric, as opposed to his views on rhetoric. It is almost a platitude that Hobbes was concerned to persuade — mainly in his political writing, but, perhaps naturally, in all facets of his work. It is a further truism that he who is concerned to persuade may be presented as the object of analysis in a discussion of his rhetoric. It is less trivial, but seems to me most obvious, that there are pertinent connections between a thinker’s views on rhetoric and his own use of rhetoric — connections which prove illuminating for both sides of the discussion.1 I shall, in this chapter, focus mainly on Hobbes’s talk of rhetoric, as related to Hobbes on language in general. Hobbes the rhetorician will make his entrance, if at all relevant, near the end of this chapter, when he tells the story of the science of politics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Such a project, of reconstructing the development of Hobbes on rhetoric as intertwined with Hobbes as rhetorician, has been admirably executed by Johnston in The Rhetoric of Leviathan ( Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986 ).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aristotle, Rhetorica,I, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Aristotle, Rhetorica, I,3.

    Google Scholar 

  4. John Aubrey, Brief Lives,p. 158.

    Google Scholar 

  5. But see John T. Harwood, The Rhetorics of Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Lamy (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), where the dubiousness of answers to such exegetic questions is brought out by the discrepancies of Hobbesian evaluation promulgated by different interpreters. Hobbes is located in a post-Ramean environment (Ramus being the principal anti-Aristotelian of the times), as one tries to understand the structure of his translation. Accordingly, Hobbes may be seen as a Ramist or as an antiRamist, depending on the arguments and texts used to ground the labels. Exegetes search for instances of Ramean terminology, anti-Ramean structure, or parallelisms with Ramean “temperament”, in the attempt to identify Hobbes within this environment. It seems to me, however, that such work is of dubious value until one is clear on the “ideology” behind the rhetoric, that is, on the reasons Hobbes had, concerning rhetoric, for being a Ramist or otherwise.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Harwood, The Rhetorics of Thomas Hobbes and Bernard Lamy,p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  7. I hasten to note, again, that local differences between Hobbes and Aristotle on specific issues in the rhetoric should not be viewed independently of the fundamental difference between Hobbes and Aristotle. Aristotle insists on a natural essence of rational, i.e. talking, and political animal. Hobbes views the rational animal as a natural essence of man, while the political is artificial. Placing the talking animal on one of two sides is the onus of my project.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Aristotle comes to mind here, telling us that educated man demands of different sciences different measures of exactitude. He differentiates between “exact” and “inexact” sciences, the latter - e.g. sociology, politology, etc. - admitting, even requiring, the use of metaphor.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For discussion of the idea that “persuasion is no longer to be contrasted to logical reasoning, nor restricted to influences that circumvent and counteract rationality”, see Jeffrey Barnouw, “Persuasion in Hobbes’s Leviathan,” Hobbes Studies I (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  11. This is not to say that Hobbes is not an able rhetorician in contexts other than that of political science. On the contrary, Hobbes’s own use of language, and specifically his use of persuasive language, are a paradigm of sophisticated rhetoric in various areas of well-defined discourse; e.g. religious discourse (Of the Kindgdome of Darknesse),history (BEHEMOTH or the Long Parliament),and law (A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common Laws of England).

    Google Scholar 

  12. On Hobbes’s use of rhetoric adapted to different audiences see Cornelis W. Schoneveld, “`Insinuations of the Will’: Hobbes’s Style and Intention in Leviathan Compared to His Earlier Political Works,” in Hobbes’s `Science of Natural Justice’,eds. Craig Walton and Paul J. Johnson (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987), and Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan.

    Google Scholar 

  13. There is an interesting literal augmentation of religious discussion which can be seen chronologically in the political writings. Elements of Law touches upon religion in three of its twenty nine chapters; De Cive devotes a whole division named RELIGION to the subject; Leviathan,besides incorporating specific chapters on religion into the two parts “Of Man” and “Of Commonwealth”, goes on to expand the issue in two full parts dealing with both theology and scriptural exegesis: “Of a Christian Common-wealth” and “Of the Kingdome of Darknesse”.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Sorell, “Hobbes’s UnAristotelian Political Rhetoric,” Philosophy and Rhetoric 23 (1990), for a similar suggestion concerning Hobbes’s use of rhetoric to facilitate easier readings of his scientific political works. Sorell presents five rhetorical devices (other than narrative) - brief summary rules, appeal to introspective experience, definitions, interpreted pieces of Scriptures, and disarmed metaphors - by which Hobbes attempted to “overcome the drawbacks of a scientific form of presentation” (p. 100).

    Google Scholar 

  15. But See Paul T. Johnson, “Leviathan’s Audience,” in Thomas Hobbes: De la Metaphysique a la Politique,eds. Martin Bertman and Michel Malherbe (Paris: J. Vrin, 1989) for an analysis of Hobbes’s audience which takes a more subtle look at the division between academic-scientific) audiences and political, religious ones.

    Google Scholar 

  16. This turn, on my part (and on Hobbes’s part), should not be mistaken for the move made by Quentin Skinner in “Thomas Hobbes: Rhetoric and the Construction of Morality,” Proceedings of the British Academy 76 (1990). While I am looking at Hobbes’s use of a rhetorical tool (the story), Skinner is involved with Hobbes’s knowledge and management of a rhetorical device in use by others in the (moral theory) tradition.

    Google Scholar 

  17. In speaking of rhetoric, I have focused on narrative as a rhetorical pattern of transmission. For a more comprehensive treatment of Hobbes’s use of rhetorical embellishments see Johnston, The Rhetoric of Leviathan,ch. 3: “Rhetoric Rediscovered: From Dry Discourse to Speaking Picture.”

    Google Scholar 

  18. See, for instance, chapter 6 on the question concerning the status of language in the solitary state. If this state is language-less how can we explain the move to a state involving speech with the aid of reason alone. It could, perhaps, be held that some speech acts (such as naming) do not involve communication. Indeed, the state of solitude may be said to contain, perhaps via such speech acts, an innate potentiality of language. This move can be countered, however, by the original doubts: how can such potentiality be brought to fulfillment? An alternative path to take would say that the state of solitude is not bereft of the rules of use of language, but their validating conditions are absent. This claim totters on similar foundations and one must then indulge in the question of the evolution of validating conditions.

    Google Scholar 

  19. At the very fundamental level of narrative being defined, it appears that discussion of the concept of time is essential. E.g. “Narrative is the representation of real and fictive events in a time sequence.” (Gerald Prince, “Aspects of a Grammar of Narrative,” Poetics Today 1, 1980, p. 49); “A salient property of narrative is double time structuring.” (Seymour Chatman, “What Novels Can Do That Films Can’t (and Vice Versa),” in On Narrative, ed. W. J. T. Mitchell, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980, p. 118); “…in a narrative neither the telling nor what is explicitly told need take time, and they suggest furthermore, that narrative reordered in any way at all is still narrative.” (Nelson Goodman, “Twisted Tales; or, Story, Study, and Symphony,” in On Narrative, p. 111); “…narrative texts: Here the signals are temporal: once upon a time, then, or the use of the preterit.” (Balz Engler, “Narrative Links in Non-Narrative Poetry,” Swiss Papers in English Language and Literature, 1984, p. 67 ).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Paul Ricoeur, “Narrative Time,” in On Narrative, ed. W. J. T. Mitchell ( Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980 ).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Biletzki, A. (1997). Eloquence is Power: The Office of Rhetoric. In: Talking Wolves. Synthese Library, vol 262. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8887-4_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8887-4_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4801-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8887-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics