Skip to main content

Reference, Experience, and Intentionality

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 237))

Abstract

The insight, due originally to Dagfinn Føllesdal, that some of Husserl’s most characteristic problems, concepts, and doctrines could be elucidated by comparing them with those of Frege was in many ways a liberation.1 Amongst other things, it provided an initial point of access to Husserl’s thoughts and texts, in the absence of which Husserl might well have continued to seem, to those of a generally ‘analytic’ orientation, either too impenetrable or too irrelevant to warrant investigation. It provided a touchstone against which certain Husserlian doctrines could be evaluated. Likewise — though this aspect has so far been little emphasized — it provided a perspective within which a balanced and critical judgement of Frege’s achievements could be formulated.2 And finally, F0llesdaFs insight has provoked and fostered a healthy curiosity about European intellectual history, and especially about the nature and origin of the socalled ‘analytic-continental’ divide that characterizes so much contemporary European thought. The invitation to compare the ideas of Husserl and Frege has clearly proved immensely valuable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See Føllesdal, D.: 1958, Husserl und Frege,

    Google Scholar 

  2. Aschehoug, Oslo; 1969, ‘Husserl’s Notion of Noema’, Journal of Philosophy, 66, pp. 680–687; 1972, ‘An Introduction to Phenomenology for Analytic Philosophers’, in R.E. Olsen and A.M. Paul (eds.), Contemporary Philosophy in Scandinavia,Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, pp. 417–429; and 1984, ‘Brentano and Husserl on Intentional Objects and Perception’, in H.L. Dreyfus (ed.), Husserl, Intentionality and Cognitive Science, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., pp. 31–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Two exceptions to this generalization are Dummett, M.A.E.: 1990, ‘Thought and Perception: The Views of Two Philosophical innovators’, in D. Bell and N. Cooper (eds.), The Analytic Tradition: Meaning, Thought and Knowledge, Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 83–103; and also Bell, D.: 1990, Husserl, Routledge, London, especially pp. 59–84.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Mohanty, J.N.: 1982, Husserl and Frege, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Harney, M.J.: Intentionality, Sense and the Mind, Nijhoff, The Hague, p. 164n.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Smith, D.W. and McIntyre, R.: 1982, Husserl and Intentionality. A Study of Mind, Meaning and Language, Reidel, Dordrecht, p. 176.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. Dreyfus, H.L.: 1984, ‘Husserl’s Perceptual Noema’, in (ed.) H.L. Dreyfus, Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science, pp. 99–100.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Given its commitment to transcendental idealism, and its reliance on the phenomenological reduction, Husserl’s philosophy after about 1910 seems less prone to misinterpretation along Fregean lines. My focus in the present paper is thus on Husserl’s early thought, and especially on the Logical Investigations.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The Oxford English Dictionary dates this usage as ‘chiefly after 1817’, and asserts that ‘its current use appears to derive from Kant’. See also entries under ‘Gegenstand’ and ‘Objekt’ in (ed.) J. Ritter: 1974, Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, Schwabe Verlag, Basel and Stuttgart.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Descartes R.: 1984, Meditations on First Philosophy, ‘Third Meditation’, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, translated by J. Cottingham, R. Stoothhoff, and Dugald Murdoch, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, volume II, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Especially Charles Renouvier. See Renouvier, C.B.: 1897, Essais de critique général, Paris, Vol I, Logique, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Brentano’s text is as follows: Jedes psychische Phänomen ist durch das charakterisiert, was die Scholastiker des Mittelalters die intentionale (auch wohl mentale)* Inexistenz eines Gegenstandes gennant haben, und was wir... die Beziehung auf einen Inhalt, die Richtung auf ein Objekt (worunter hier nicht eine Realität zu verstehen ist), oder die immanente Gegenständlichkeit nennen würden. Jedes enthält etwas als Objekt in sich....

    Google Scholar 

  13. Sie gebrauchen auch den Ausdruck ‘gegenständlich (objektive) in etwas sein’, der, wenn man sich jetzt seiner bedienen wollte, umgekehrt als Bezeichnung einer wirklichen Existenz außerhalb des Geistes genommen werden dürfte. Doch erinnert daran der Ausdruck ‘immanent gegenständlich sein’, den man zuweilen in ähnlichem Sinne gebraucht, und bei welchem offenbar das ‘immanent’ das zu fürchtende Mißverständnis ausschließen soll. Brentano, F.: 1874, Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, Duncker und Humblot, Leipzig, Vol I, Book 2, eh. 1, §5.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, Vol II, Book 2, ch. 5, §2n.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, Vol I, Book 1, ch. 1, §2.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Quotations from Husserl’s Logical Investigations are cited as follows: LU refers to the pagination in Husserl, E.: 1984, Logische Untersuchungen, Zweiter Band, U. Panzer (ed.), Nijhoff, The Hague. LI refers to the pagination in Husserl, E.: 1970, Logical Investigations, translated by J.N. Findlay, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Frege, G.: 1964, The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, translated by M. Furth, University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles, pp. 10–25; and 1984, ‘Thoughts’ in Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, B. McGuinness (ed.), Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 351–372. See also Husserl, LU pp. 110, 130; LI pp. 333, 353.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Frege, G.: 1984, ‘Review of E.G. Husserl, Philosophie der Arithmetik r, in Collected Papers, p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Husserl, E.: 1931, Ideas. General Introduction to Phenomenology, translated by W.R. Boyce Gibson, George Allen & Unwin, London, pp. 407–8.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Frege, G.: 1984, ‘On Sense and Meaning’, in Collected Papers, p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Frege, G.: 1984, ‘On Sense and Meaning’, Collected Papers, p. 163.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Küng, G.: 1977, ‘The Phenomenological Reduction as Epoche and Explication’, in F.A. Elliston and P. McCormick (eds.), Husserl: Expositions and Appraisals, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, p. 341.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See, for example, LU pp. 6, 14, 23, 26, 381, and 765; LI pp. 249, 255, 261, 264, 556, and 862.

    Google Scholar 

  24. The greater part of Investigations I, II, V, and VI are in fact explicitly devoted to the provision of phenomenological analyses of such objectivity concepts as knowledge, evidence, truth, existence, object, Meaning, Species, state of affairs, and the like.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Husserl, E.: 1987, Vorlesungen liber Bedeutungslehre. Sommersemester 1908, U. Panzer (ed.), Nijhoff, The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Intentionaler Gegenstand als solcher. In fact I use the English phrase to capture the whole family of notions that Husserl employs in this connection: the intentional object as intended; the meant objectivity as meant; the object in the How of its determinations, and so forth.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Dummett, M.A.E.: 1991, ‘Critical Notice of D. Bell, HusserV, Philosophical Quarterly, 41, pp. 485–488.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Der vermeinte (oder intentionale) Gegenstand schlechthin. Husserl sometimes talks in this connection of “der Gegenstand-worüber” or “der Gegenstand, welcher intendiert ist” (see, e.g., LU p. 414, and Bedeutungslehre pp. 41, 66f, 166).

    Google Scholar 

  29. For elucidation of the notion of intentional identity, see Geach, P.T.: 1972, ‘Intentional Identity’ and ‘The Perils of Pauline’, in Logic Matters, Blackwell, Oxford, pp. 146–165.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Husserl, E.: 1987, Bedeutungslehre, p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Husserl, E.: 1987, Bedeutungslehre, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See, for example, LU pp. 10, 29, and 535; LI pp. 252, 266, and 663.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Husserl, E.: 1987, Bedeutungslehre, p. 46; also p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See LU pp. 26, 427, and 439; LI pp. 264, 587, and 596.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See references cited above, footnote 21.

    Google Scholar 

  36. These two errors are summarized very clearly at LU p. 385; LI p.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1994 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bell, D. (1994). Reference, Experience, and Intentionality. In: Haaparanta, L. (eds) Mind, Meaning and Mathematics. Synthese Library, vol 237. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8334-3_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8334-3_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4366-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8334-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics