Advertisement

Inductive Logic Revisited

  • Jacques-Paul Dubucs
Chapter
Part of the Philosophical Studies Series book series (PSSP, volume 56)

Abstract

The main objective of inductive logic is to give a satisfactory analysis of the intuitive relation of confirmation, which relates two sentences when one supports the other without the truth of the first one being however logically (in the sense of deductive logic) inconsistent with the falsity of the second one. Carnap has tried to build such an inductive logic, the seminal idea of which was the conformity of the relation of confirmation to the principles of the calculus of probability. This attempt gave rise to many difficulties, and it is today widely considered as a dead end. I would like to show that this opinion is not definitely well-founded, and that Carnap’s construction may be cleared from much of this criticism provided some slight alterations are accepted.

Keywords

Inductive Logic Deductive Logic Conditional Logic Partial Deducibility Normal Notion 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Adams, E.W. (1975) Logic of Conditionals. Reidel, Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Barwise, J., Cooper, R. (1981) Generalized Quantifiers and Natural Language. Linguistics and Philosophy, IV, 159–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Benthem, J. van (1984) Foundations of conditional Logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, XIII, 303–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carnap, R. (1945) On Inductive Logic. Philosophy of Science, XII, 72–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. (1950) Logical Foundations of Probability. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.Google Scholar
  6. Dubois, D., Prade, H. (1991) A Glance at Non-Standard Models and Logics of Uncertainty and Vagueness. This book.Google Scholar
  7. Dubucs, J.-P. (1990) Carnapes ab Omni Naevo Vindicatus. Cahiers du C.R.E.A., XIV, 97–120.Google Scholar
  8. Goodman, N. (1954) Fact, Fiction, Forecast. Athlone Press, London, 73–120.Google Scholar
  9. Hintikka, J. (1965) Towards a Theory of Inductive Generalization. In Y. Bar-Hillel (ed.), Proceedings of the 1964 Congress for Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 274–288.Google Scholar
  10. Levi, I. (1986) Probabilistic Pettifoggery. Erkenntnis XXV, 133–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Pearl, J. (1989) Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference. Morgan Kaufmann, San Mateo, CA.Google Scholar
  12. Polya, G. (1954) Mathematics and Plausible Reasoning I. Induction and Analogy in Mathematics. Princeton U.P.Google Scholar
  13. Popper, K.R., Miller, D. (1983) A Proof of the Impossibility of Inductive Probability. Nature, Vol 302, No 5910, 21 April 1983, 387–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Popper, K.R., Miller D. (1987) Why Probabilistic Support is not Inductive. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. A 321, 569–591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Westerstahl, D. (1989) Quantifiers in Formal and Natural Languages. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenther (eds), Handbook of Philosophical Logic IV, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1–131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Zwirn, D. & H. (199?) Metaconfirmation, to appear.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 1993

Authors and Affiliations

  • Jacques-Paul Dubucs
    • 1
  1. 1.C.N.R.S.University of Paris I-SorbonneFrance

Personalised recommendations