Advertisement

Causal Laws are Objectifications of Inductive Schemes

  • Wolfgang Spohn
Chapter
Part of the Philosophical Studies Series book series (PSSP, volume 56)

Abstract

And this paper is an attempt to say precisely how, thus addressing a philosophical problem which is commonly taken to be a serious one. It does so, however, in quite an idiosyncratic way. It is based on the account of inductive schemes I have given in (1988) and 1990a) and on the conception of causation I have presented in (1980), (1983), and (1990b), and it intends to fill one of many gaps which have been left by these papers.

Keywords

Epistemic State Sufficient Reason Objective Probability Direct Causation Belief Function 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Aronson, J.L. (1971), “On the Grammar of ‘Cause’ ”, Synthese 22, 414–430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beauchamp, T., A. Rosenberg (1981), Hume and the Problem of Causation, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Carnap, R. (1966), Philosophical Foundations of Physics, Basic Books, New York.Google Scholar
  4. Diaconis, P., D. Freedman (1980), “De Finetti’s Theorem for Markov Chains”, Annals of Probability, 115–130.Google Scholar
  5. Fair, D. (1979), “Causation and the Flow of Energy”, Erkenntnis 14, 219–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. van Fraassen, B.C. (1980), The Scientific Image, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. van Fraassen, B.C. (1989), Laws and Symmetry, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Gärdenfors, P. (1988), Knowledge in Flux, M.I.T. Press, Cambridge, Mass.Google Scholar
  9. Hansson, S.O. (1991), “The Logic of Repeated Belief Changes”, forthcoming.Google Scholar
  10. Hempel, C.G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, Free Press, New York.Google Scholar
  11. Hume, D. (1739), A Treatise Concerning Human Nature. Page numbers refer to the 2nd edition by P.H. Nidditch of the edition by L. A. Selby-Bigge, Oxford University Press 1978.Google Scholar
  12. Hume, D. (1977), An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Google Scholar
  13. Kripke, S. (1972), “Naming and Necessity”, in: D. Davidson, G. Harman (eds.), Semantics of Natural Language, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 253–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Lewis, D. (1973), “Causation”, Journal of Philosophy 70, 556–567; also in Lewis (1986), pp. 159–172, supplemented by postscripts.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Lewis, D. (1980), “A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective Chance”, in: R.C. Jeffrey (ed.), Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, vol. II, University of California Press, pp. 263–293; also in Lewis (1986), pp. 83–113, supplemented by postscripts.Google Scholar
  16. Lewis, D. (1986), Philosophical Papers, vol. II, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Mackie, J.L. (1974), The Cement of Universe, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Mill, J. St. (1843), System of Logic. Google Scholar
  19. Mühlhölzer, F. (1988), “On Objectivity”, Erkenntnis 28, 185–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Putnam, H. (1983a), “Why There Isn’t a Ready-Made World”, in: H. Putnam, Realism and Reason, Philosophical Papers, vol. 3, Cambridge University Press, ch. 12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Putnam, H. (1983b), “Why Reason Can’t Be Naturalized”, in: H. Putnam, Realism and Reason, Philosophical Papers, vol. 3, Cambridge University Press, ch. 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Quine, W.V.O. (1969), “Natural Kinds”, in W.V.O. Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, Columbia University Press, New York, ch. 5.Google Scholar
  23. Salmon, W.C. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Shenoy, P. (1989), “On Spohn’s Rule for Revision of Beliefs”, School of Business Working Paper No. 213, University of Kansas, Lawrence.Google Scholar
  25. Skyrms, B. (1984), Pragmatics and Empiricism, Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Spohn, W. (1980), “Stochastic Independence, Causal Independence, and Shieldability”, Journal of Philosophical Logic 9, 73–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Spohn, W. (1983), “Deterministic and Probabilistic Reasons and Causes”, in: C.G. Hempel, H. Putnam, W.K. Essler (eds.), Methodology, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science. Essays in Honour of Wolfgang Stegmüller on the Occasion of his 60th Birthday, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 371–396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Spohn, W. (1988), “Ordinal Conditional Functions. A Dynamic Theory of Epistemic States”, in: W.L. Harper, B. Skyrms (eds.), Causation in Decision, Belief Change, and Statistics, vol. II, Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 105–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Spohn, W. (1990a), “A General Non-Probabilistic Theory of Inductive Reasoning”, in R.D. Schachter, T.S. Levitt, J. Lemmer, L.N. Kanal (eds.), Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence 4, Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp. 149–158.Google Scholar
  30. Spohn, W. (1990b), “Direct and Indirect Causes”, Topoi 9, 125–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Spohn, W. (1993), “Wie kann die Theorie der Rationalität normativ und empirisch zugleich sein?”, in: L. Eckensberger, U. Gähde (eds.), Ethik und Empirie. Zum Zusammenspiel von begrifflicher Analyse und erfahrungswissenschaftlicher Forschung in der Ethik, Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M., to appear.Google Scholar
  32. Tooley, M. (1987), Causation, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 1993

Authors and Affiliations

  • Wolfgang Spohn
    • 1
  1. 1.University of BielefeldGermany

Personalised recommendations