Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • 119 Accesses

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 232))

Abstract

This book deals with a basic problem arising within the Bayesian approach to scientific methodology, namely the choice of prior probabilities.1 The problem will be considered with special reference to some inference methods used within Bayesian statistics (BS) and the so-called theory of inductive probabilities (TIP).2 In this study an important role will be played by the assumption — defended by Sir Karl Popper and the supporters of the current verisimilitude theory (VT) — that the cognitive goal of science is the achievement of a high degree of truthlikeness or verisimilitude.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. After World War II the Bayesian approach has gained increasing support among statisticians and epistemologists. In particular, in the last fifteen year the Bayesian approach to epistemology has been developed by several authors such as Rosenkrantz (1977,1981), Horwich (1982), Levi (1980), Howson and Urbach (1989). Although the contention between the Bayesian approach and other statistical and epistemological approaches is an intriguing topic (see, for instance, Barnett (1973), Howson and Urbach (1989), Earman (1992)) it is not my topic since my concern in this book is with problems arising within the Bayesian approach.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The theory of inductive probabilities (developed by Carnap and other epistemologists) deals with certain types of inductive inferences, such as prediction of future events, which are also typical subjects in philosophical research on induction. In particular, the problem of assessing the probability of a future event - which had already been considered by Hobbes (1650) - has received much attention after it was studied by Hume (1739): see Hacking (1975, p. 48 and 178).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Following a common epistemological usage, here “hypothesis” refers to whatever factual statement, from specific predictions to highly general theories. On the contrary, in statistics “hypothesis” is typically used with a much narrower meaning. Unfortunately, many other terminological conflicts occur between epistemology and statistics. Although I tried to make the text sufficiently clear to readers with a background in any of the two fields, a bias towards the epistemological jargon was inevitable given my own background. Hence, some tolerance is requested to those readers who will find familiar terms employed with a unfamiliar meaning (or vice versa).

    Google Scholar 

  4. This term is used, among others, by Swinburne (1973) and Skyrms (1966).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Of course scientists qua human beings pursue non-cognitive goals even within their scientific activity. For instance, “many people called scientists regard science as some battlefield where `being regarded as clever and correct’ is more important than `really having done all the work”’ (Prof. W. Schaafsma, private communication).

    Google Scholar 

  6. The notion of cognitive context is borrowed from Levi (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Empiricist philosophers such as Francis Bacon and rationalist philosophers such as Descartes, although holding different views about the nature of scientific method, shared the same infallibilistic view - which Watkins (1978, p. 25) calls the “Bacon-Descartes ideal” - about the goal of science. The infallibilistic ideal was also advocated by scientists and philosophers such as Boyle, Locke and Newton.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Here “the truth” is intended in the sense of the correspondence theory of truth suggested by Aristotle and accepted, more or less explicitly, by most infallibilists: a statement is true if and only if it corresponds with reality, i.e., with the way things really are. According to the infallibilistic view the scientific method, if properly used, infallibly guarantees the discovery of true theories (see Laudan, 1973, p. 277).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Indeed certainty about a given statement may be seen as the maximum degree of belief in the truth of the statement.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For instance, Descartes (ca. 1628) maintains that we should “reject… merely probable knowledge and make it a rule to trust only what is completely known and incapable to be doubted.”

    Google Scholar 

  11. A fascinating inquiry into the `emergence of probability’ in modern thought is made by Hacking (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  12. The origins of the concept of verisimilitude and, more generally, the fallibilistic methodologies are traced by Niiniluoto ( 1987, Ch. 5).

    Google Scholar 

  13. It would appear that in the last century a number of philosophers had already recognized that the probabilistic and verisimilitude views are not incompatible (see Laudan, 1973, pp. 285–286 and 295). However, according to Laudan (ibid.,p. 286) “these two approaches did… represent different emphases, and were to give rise in the twentieth century to two very different strains in philosophy of science (Carnap and Keynes being the descendants of the progress by probabilification school, and Popper and Reichenbach focusing primarily on progress by self-correction)”.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Another example of a co-ordinated development of the Bayesian approach and the verisimilitude theory is given by the notions of expected verisimilitude and probable verisimilitude which can be defined using the concepts of epistemic probability and verisimilitude (see Chapter 4.3).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Following a common epistemological usage, here “inference” is employed in the sense “argument”. This conflicts with the more frequent statistical usage of “inference” in the sense of “conclusion” (cf. note 3).

    Google Scholar 

  16. The conclusion of an inductive inference, indeed, is frequently termed “hypothesis” because of its conjectural character.

    Google Scholar 

  17. As pointed out by Hacking ( 1975, Chapter 2), since its emergence in the Western thought probability was essentially dual, on the one hand having to do with degrees of belief (epistemic probability), on the other, with devices tending to produce stable long-run frequencies (physical or objective probability).

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Chapter 2.1 and Chapter 11, note 4.

    Google Scholar 

  19. The term “Generalized Carnapian (GC-)systems” is borrowed from Kuipers (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Chapter 7, note 18.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Gini diversity is a measure of the degree of disorder of a population or process (for a more detailed description see Chapter 10). Contrary to what one might believe at first sight, Est[G(q)] is different from Gini diversity G(y°) of the prior vector y°: see formula (8.7) and Chapter 8, note 5.

    Google Scholar 

  22. On the other hand idealizations - which play a basic role in empirical sciences - may be very useful also in methodological analysis. This basically depends on the possibility of finding interesting generalizations and `concretization’ of the proposed idealizations (cf. Chapter 11 where some possible extensions of the present approach to EPO are suggested).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1993 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Festa, R. (1993). Introduction. In: Optimum Inductive Methods. Synthese Library, vol 232. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8131-8_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8131-8_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4318-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8131-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics