Skip to main content

Rationality and the Correctness of a Decision of the Application of Law

  • Chapter
The Judicial Application of Law

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 15))

  • 237 Accesses

Abstract

The problem of rationality is implied in the theoretical analysis of the judicial application of law. Justification of a judicial decision is the one way of demonstrating the rationality of the decision and at the same time acting as a control on that rationality. Rationality analysed through the justification of decisions is based on the existence of rules of justificatory reasoning. These show the form of the decision by defining the way of inferring the conclusion from its premisses (par 2 below). Controversies about the legal syllogism are linked in part to the simplified conception of this reasoning as a syllogism of subsumption (Ch IX.1.1) and in part to divergent opinions about the role of particular kinds of logic in legal reasoning (par 3 below).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. K. O. Apel, 1979; M. Bunge, 1987; J. Habermas, 1979, 1981, p. 344; K. Lehrer and C. Wagner, 1981, pp. 7–13; G. March, 1986, part II; as the key-concept of the social sciences, A. Schütz, 1964, p. 69; rationality constraint as the most basic law of psychology, C. Cherniak, 1986, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  2. MTJD, pp. 49–70; SHD, Ch II; R. Alexy, 1978, part C, Ch II; A. Aarnio, 1987, Ch III.4; M. Zirk-Sadowski, 1984, Ch 4–6.

    Google Scholar 

  3. J. Wróblewski, 1986, 1907a, pp. 129–140.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf., in general J. Kmital and L. Nowak 1968, Ch II, par 3; Ch III, IV; J. Giedymin, 1964, p. 126ff; H. Simon, 1957, Ch 15; T. Kotarbiński, 1955, p. 137ff; for legal discourse L. Nowak, 1973, Ch IV.2; G. Gottlieb, 1968, p. 25ff, 154ff, 166ff; P. A. Freund, 1968, Ch 5; T. Schwartz, 1986; J. Elster, 1986; for interpretation J. Lenoble and F. Ost, 1980, part I, title II; rationality is linked with reasonability, cf., A Aarnio, 1987, Ch V.2; R. E. MacKerrow, 1982; J. Bell, 1986; S. K. Laughlin and D. T. Hughes, 1986; Ch. Perelman, 1979b, Ch 11.

    Google Scholar 

  5. On coherence cf., N. MacCormick, 1978, Ch VIII, pp. 227–270; a special notion of coherence, A. Peczenik, 1989, Ch 4.1; 4.2.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Future knowledge is important in any consequentialist argument, N. MacCormick, 1978, Ch VI; R. S. Summers, 1978, pp. 735–742; J. Wróblewski, 1987a, p. 152; prognosis is especially relevant for criminal law P. Zakrzewski, 1964, and critically about its level in Poland M. Szerer, 1969, p. 171; K. Buchała, 1964, pp. 13, 40; on the “enigma of the future” H. M. Hart and J. T. Mc Naughton, 1958, p. 68ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. J. Dawson, 1968, p. XI; J. Esser, 1964, p. 85; MTJD, p. 49ff; SHD, p. 35ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. R. Wasserstrom, 1961, p. 24; T. Eckhoff and K. D. Jacobsen, 1960, p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  9. In any choice there is a “residuo irrazionale” A. Giuliani, 1966, p. 161, cf., in moral choice L. Bagolini, 1968, pp. 36ff, 47, 436, 439; there is no problem of irrationality in “legal cognition”, C. Cossio, 1964, p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf., note (IX) 8, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf., bibliography in J. Kalinowski, 1972; R. Alexy, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  12. ZTP, Ch IX, par.1.3; J. Wróblewski, 1973b, 1989a, Ch 7.3; Z. Ziembirński, 1980, Ch 2.2.

    Google Scholar 

  13. M. Hempoliński, 1974; N. MacCormick and O. Weinberger, 1986, Ch II; J. Woleński, 1980, Ch II; hermeneutical trend A. Aarnio, 1983, Ch 2, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Z. Ziemba, 1984, Ch 14; R. Hernandez Marin, 1984, Ch 4; a non-linguistic conception of norm J. Woleński, 1980, Ch III; Ch. and O. Weinberger, 1979, Ch 7; K. Opałek, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  15. I. Tammelo, 1969, p. 38; I. Tammelo and F. Schreiner, 1974, vol. 1 p. 16ff; 1977. vol. 2, p. 51ff; Ch. and O. Weinberger, 1979, p. 100, par 7.3.1(3).

    Google Scholar 

  16. On pragmatical adequacy of the calculus J. Woleński, 1980, p. 63ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. J. Brkic, 1985, Ch 3; G. di Bernardo, 1972, Ch IV-VII; J. L. Gardies, 1979a, book 1, Ch III, book 2; G. Kalinowski, 1972a Ch 1; 1972b Ch III-V; A Soeteman, 1989, Ch III-VI; I. Tammelo, 1978, part I; Z. Ziemba, 1984, Ch 1, 5, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  18. C. E. Alchourron, 1965; C. E. Alchourron and D. Mackinson, 1981; G. Kalinowski, 1965, Ch IV.3; I. Tammelo, 1978, part II; J. Woleński, 1980, Ch IV; Z. Ziemba, 1984, Ch7,12.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ch. Perelman-L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1958; Ch. Perelman, 1963, 1977, 1970a, 1979b, 1980; R. Alexy, 1978, part A, Ch IV; J. Brkic, 1985, Ch 2; J. A. Blair and R. H. Johnson, 1980; J. Horowitz, 1972; L. Gianformaggio, 1976, Ch 3, 1983; J. Lenoble and F. Ost, 1980, Ch II, titre 1; A. Giuliani, 1970; M. Taruffo, 1975, Ch IV.2.3; A. Soeteman, 1989, Ch I, IX; O. Weinberger, 1973; J. Wróblewski, 1986; for topics Th. Viehweg, 1965; G. Struck, 1971; T. M. Seibert, 1982; O. Ballweg, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ch. Perelman, 1979a, par 46–48.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ch. Perelman, 19791, par 3, 4; cf., a criticism of “logicism”, L. Lombardi Vallauri, 1981, p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ch. Perelman, 1970, Ch XV.

    Google Scholar 

  23. O. Weinberger, 1970, p. 318.

    Google Scholar 

  24. A. Aarnio, 1977, Ch II; 1987, Ch IV.2; L. Gianformaggio, 1986, Ch 3, 4; L. Morawski, 1988, part I; A. Peczenik, 1989; J. Wróblewski, 1978b, pp. 119–122, 130–132; 1989 f.

    Google Scholar 

  25. O. Weinberger, 1978, p. 128; N. MacCormick and O. Weinberger, 1986, pp. 16, 154ff; in general G. Kalinowski, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  26. K. Ajdukiewicz, 1965, par 56–58.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ch. Perelman, 1979a, par 3–5; J. Wróblewski, 1973b, pp. 53–58; cf., note (VII) 62.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf., a concise description of non-aletic logic, G. Kalinowski, 1972a, Ch III-V.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cultural interpretation, J. Kmita, 1973, part I, Ch 1, part II, Ch 2 part 4, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  30. SC 23.09.1969 III UZP 2/69 OSPIKA 1970 U 23; SC 24.09.1969 III UZP 1/69 OSPIKA 1970 U 24.

    Google Scholar 

  31. SC 03.09.1965 VI KZP 36/65 OSPIKA 1966 K 74.

    Google Scholar 

  32. SC 01.04.1967 VI KZP 4/67 OSPIKA 1967 K 294.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Argumentation against “mixed reasoning”, F. Studnicki, 1967, p. 124ff.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Z. Ziemba, 1984, p. 232.

    Google Scholar 

  35. N. Bobbio, 1938; U. Klug, 1958, par 9; G. Kalinowski, 1965, Ch IV, par 3B; F. Bydlinski, book 3, part 1, Ch II, III; J. Nowacki, 1966; A. Peczenik, 1989, Ch 7.4; E. Waśkowski, 1936, Ch III, par 4; formalisation of this reasoning, L. Reisinger, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ch. Perelman, 1979a, para 68; 1980, Ch 1.

    Google Scholar 

  37. On the contrast between of analogy intra legem and extra legem J. Nowacki, 1966, Ch I, II; analogy as an idirect application of law G. Burchardi, 1869, p. 96ff; fuzziness of delimitation of gap-filling and interpretation K. Larenz, 1964, pp. 385, 400, 404.

    Google Scholar 

  38. ZTW, Ch VI, par 2.2; J. M. Broekman, 1985; F. Bydlinski, 1982, book 3, part 3, Ch I; A. G. Conte, 1962, part II; N. Bobbio, 1960, Ch IV; L. Lombardi Vallauri, 1981, Ch I.2; S. Rundstein, 1904, Ch III; Ch. Perelman, 1968; J. Nowacki, 1970; I. Tammelo, 1959; L. Recasens Siches, 1969, p. 324; Z. Ziembiński, 1980, Ch 4.5.1; a sociological point of view cf., N. Luhmann, 1985, p. 282ff; ontological justification of completeness C. Cossio, 1964, pp. 403ff, 656, 676.

    Google Scholar 

  39. ZTW, pp. 309–316; ZTP, Ch III.4; J. Wróblewski, 1972a.

    Google Scholar 

  40. S. Rundstein, 1904, p. 43ff; J. Nowacki, 1970; F. Somlo, 1917, p. 404ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. ZTW, p. 315; J. Nowacki, 1970, p. 36; This type of gap in SC 18.04.1963 I CR 223/63 OSPIKA 1965 C 6.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf., decisions of the Supreme Court cited in J. Nowacki, 1969, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  43. SC 20.03.1969 III PZP 2/69 OSPIKA 1969 C 224; “... a use of analogy is permitted if it can be said there is a gap in a statute”; the differences of opinion concerning a use of analogy when there is no explicit regulation e.g., the bench of 7 judges against the simple bench in SC 20.09.1965 III CO 5/64 OSPIKA 1966 C 160.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Axiological premisses of analogy H. Heller, 1961, p. 89ff; J. Nowacki, 1966, Ch VIII.

    Google Scholar 

  45. J. Nowacki, 1966, Ch VIII; against the elimination of analogy in penal law E. Huber, 1925, p. 390, note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  46. No analogy is justified when the law is definite SC 15.12.1966 II PR 495/66 OSPIKA 1967 C 194; SC 15.03.1965 III PO 45/63 OSPIKA 1966 C 36; cf., opposite views of legal doctrine in comments by A. Szpunar and S. Grzybowski concerning SC 13.12.1962 II CR 1006/62 OSPIKA 1964 C 91.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Cf., judicial decisions analysed in J. Nowacki, 1966c.

    Google Scholar 

  48. ZIP, Ch VIII.4.2.3; U. Klug, 1968, par 10, 11; A. Ross, 1958, p. 148ff; E. Waśkowski, 1936, Ch III.3; J. Wróblewski, 1965a; it is doubtful whether analogy is the rule and a contrario argument the exception as is maintains by A. Baumgarten, 1939, p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  49. SC 16.08.1969 I CZ 78/69 OSPIKA 1970 C 99; SC 02.02.1968 II KR 179/67 OSPIKA 1970 K 126; against the incorrect use of a contrario argument SC 09.09.1967 III CZP 38/67 OSPIKA 1969 C 154.

    Google Scholar 

  50. “Systemic rules” could be also treated as assumptions of decision because of the elasticity of the indentification of assumptions and rules.

    Google Scholar 

  51. There are controversies concerning the choice of rules serving as the basis of analogy SC 21.10.1959 VI KO 1/59 OSPIKA 1961 K 135 with the comment by A Murzynowski.

    Google Scholar 

  52. U. Klug, 1958, par 12; G. Kalinowski, 1965, Ch IV. 3b, aa; A. Peczenik, 1962; C. E. Alchourron, 1965; similarity of per analogism and a fortiori arguments stated early in C. Brocher 1870 p. 210; SC 27.04.1982 UI URN 74/82 OSPIKA 1983 P 182. cf., note (IX) 20.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Use of argumentum a maiori ad minus SC 05.03.1966 VI KZP 69/65 OSPIKA 1967 K 39; SC 23.08.1968 III CZP 69/68 OSPIKA 1970 C 84; a criticism of the use of this argument SC 20.12.1967 III CZP 84/67 OSPIKA 1968 C 262.

    Google Scholar 

  54. SC 16.12.1966 VI KZP 23/66 OSPIKA 1967 K 199.

    Google Scholar 

  55. SC 22.02.1959 VI KO 1/59 OSPIKA 1960 K 211; SC 13.04.1961 VI KO 19/61 OSPIKA 1961 K 237.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf., The use of argumentum a maiori in the first instance court and of analogy in the supreme Court SC 31.12.1962 II CR 1006/62 OSPIKA 1964 C 91. Commenting on this (SC 13.02.1968 VI KZP 17/67 OSPIKA 1969 K 261) M. Cieślak, in approving of the decision, accepts the use of argumentum ad minus but stresses that the use of analogy would result in a different decision.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Cf., note (IX) 3 5.

    Google Scholar 

  58. J. Wróblewski, 1983a.

    Google Scholar 

  59. J. Wróblewski, 1983a, pp. 239–243.

    Google Scholar 

  60. J. Wróblewski, 1983a, pp. 247–252.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Cf., note 20 above.

    Google Scholar 

  62. J. Wróblewski, 1986a.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ch. Perelman, 1977, Ch XVI; 1979b, Ch 1–4; 1979a, Ch 15–17.

    Google Scholar 

  64. V. Villa, 1984, Ch V.

    Google Scholar 

  65. A. Aarnio, 1977, Ch II. 1.2; N. MacCormick, 1978, Ch IX; 1983; J. Wróblewski, 1979b, process of proof J. Wróblewski, 1981c, L. Morawski, 1983.

    Google Scholar 

  66. ZTP, Ch VIII; J. Wróblewski 1974a, K. Engisch, 1960, pp. 22–37; J. Wróblewski, 1965, pp. 171–175; U. Klug, 1958, par 5; “prudential syllogism”, J. Kalinowski, 1967b, p. 174; A. Giuliani, 1966, pp. 159, 172; L. Gianformaggio, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  67. L. Brutt, 1907, p. 39: “Die konkrete Rechtsfolge ergibt sich... syllogistisch aus dem Rechtssatz und der konkrete Tatbestand nach der ersten aristotelischen Figur Modus I.. Cf., F. Castberg, 1957, pp. 52ff, 62ff; E. Garcia Maynez, 1960, p. 321ff; O. Lathinen, 1957, pp. 157, 159; S. Rundstein, 1916, p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  68. A realist criticism of syllogism G. Casper, 1967, p. 27ff.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Syllogism as the necessary heuristic and justificatory argument M. P. Fabreguettes, 1914, p. 482; as ex post rationalisation, L. Recasens Siches, 1959, p. 317; as justification ex post R. Cross, 1961, pp. 202, 204; G. W. Paton, 1969, p. 161; J. W. Salmond, 1966, p., 183.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Cf., note (II)4, 9.

    Google Scholar 

  71. The syllogistic approach was primarily linked with the mechanistic idea of the application of law anticipated by Abelard (A. Giuliani, 1966, Ch IV) and treating the controversy decided by the court as a theoretical problem resolved by reference to a system of norms (A. Giuliani, 1968, p. 237ff). My approach is not linked to these historical ideas.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Against conception of the legal syllogism presented here, the criticism of J. C. Cueto-Rua, 1961, p. 138 is not relevant, cf, also L. Nowak, 1970, pp. 169–171.

    Google Scholar 

  73. B. N. Cardozo, 1957, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  74. It is connected with a subsumptive model of decision-making, cf., T. Eckhoff and K. D. Jackobsen, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  75. This is why O. Brusiin was right when he said that the legal syllogism “... ist eine überaus starke Vereinfachung” (O. Brusiin, 1957, p. 106).

    Google Scholar 

  76. Sprawnosc postpowania sa̧dowego 1974, p. 121.

    Google Scholar 

  77. J. Wróblewski, 1985c.

    Google Scholar 

  78. In civil cases justification of the regional courts decisions are “... are of average or below average quality, and in 5% are contradictory with art. 328, para 2 code of civil procedure” which formulates the criteria of proper justification. Sprawnosc postgpowania sa̧dowego 1974, p. 121.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Cf., notes 133, 134 below.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Cf., notes 136, 137 below.

    Google Scholar 

  81. M. Taruffo, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  82. SC 23.02.1982 III CZP 3/82 OSPIKA 1983 C 114.

    Google Scholar 

  83. SC 04.03.1983 III CZP 7/83 C 148. cf., note (VII)4.

    Google Scholar 

  84. SC 28.02.1983 II DR 25/83 OSPIKA 1983 K 226.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Cf., notes (VIII) 122–129.

    Google Scholar 

  86. SC 21.03.1983 II KR 48/83 OSPIKA 1983 K 59.

    Google Scholar 

  87. SC 10.05.1982 Rw 317/82 OSPIKA 1983 K 34.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Cf., note (VII)80; (VIII)122.

    Google Scholar 

  89. SC 21.03.1983 II KR 48/83 OSPIKA 1983 K 59.

    Google Scholar 

  90. SC 19.11.1982 II CR 449/82 OSPIKA 1983 C 156.

    Google Scholar 

  91. SC 14.07.1983 VI KZP 19/83 OSPIKA 1984 K 94.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Cf., postulates of L. Petrażycki. 1960. vol. 2. par 39: H. Kelsen. 1960, n. 239.

    Google Scholar 

  93. A reduction of the theory of law to a theory of sources of law in a moderate version of the free law school F. Geny, 1932; a positivistic approach A. Ross, 1922, Ch XII–XVI; a kind of realistic approach to the sources of law A. Peczenik, 1989, Ch 6; singling out the main meanings of the term “source of law”, J. Wróblewski, 1974e.

    Google Scholar 

  94. J. Wróblewski, 1974e, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  95. J. Wróblewski 1984b, p. 262ff.

    Google Scholar 

  96. A typology inspired by Scandinavian practice, A. Peczenik, 1983, Ch 2.2.2; 1989, Ch 6.2.

    Google Scholar 

  97. J. Wróblewski 1985a, pp. 25–28.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Cf., the enumeration of several functions by S. Wiodyka in his comment to SC 25.09.1967 III CZP 117/66 OSPIKA 1968 C 195.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Cf., an approval of the decision with a rejection of its justification in comments by: A. Ohanowicz to SC 24.04.1964 II CR 176/64 OSPIKA 1965 C 229; by A. Szpunar to SC 28.08.1968 II CR 318/68 OSPIKA 1969 C 201; commenting on SC 13.12.1962 II CR 1006/62 OSPIKA 1964 C 91, A. Szpunar and S. Grzybowski have different opinions concerning its proper justification.

    Google Scholar 

  100. W. Siedlecki, 1969, p. 372 discusses complex problems of justification in the case of “extraordinary revision”.

    Google Scholar 

  101. G. Gorla, 1968, vol. 1, p. 123ff.

    Google Scholar 

  102. The stability of judicial decisions is related to the “principle of inertia” Ch. Perelman, 1979b, p. 131; 198z, pp. 28, 159, 169ff.

    Google Scholar 

  103. SC 25.02.1969 KRN 182/68 OSN-kar 10, 1969; SC 10.10.1968 IV KR 106/68 OSN-kar 7–8, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Legal language uses the term “legal basis”, e.g., art 372 para lc.c.p., “factual basis” and “legal basis” art 328 para 2 c.c.proc; cf., A. Zieliski, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  105. J. Wróblewski, 1969a, 1971b, a reference to a valid rule is treated as a “doctrine of legalistic justification” by D. Lyons, 1984, p. 178; from a psychological standpoint A. W. Simpson, 1961, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  106. J. Wróblewski, 1971b, my rule of decision is not the same as the Entscheidungsnorm according to E. Ehrlich, 1913, p. 140ff.

    Google Scholar 

  107. SC 03.10.1966 III CZP 17/66 OSPIKA 1968 C 28; SC 03.05.1966 III CO 12/66 OSPIKA 1967 C 2; SC 27.06.1969 III CZP 34/67 OSPIKA 1970 C 94.

    Google Scholar 

  108. The problem of retroactivity in SC 07.03.1966 III CO 72/65 OSPIKA 1966 C 273; SC 14.05.1965 III TR 2028/64 OSPIKA U 90 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  109. SC 18.06.1966 VI KZP 10/66 OSPIKA 1969 K 74.

    Google Scholar 

  110. E.g., the application of art 44 crim.c. (1932) at two levels and the rejection of its applicability by the Supreme Court SC 26.08.1967 V KRN 756/67 OSPIKA 1968 K 39; applicability of rules more favourable to the accused SC 14.01.1970 III KR 185/69 OSPIKA 1970 K 163; cf., P. A. Coté, 1982, part 1, Ch 2.

    Google Scholar 

  111. SC 10.05.1968 VI KZP 2/67 OSPIKA 1969 K 68.

    Google Scholar 

  112. J. Wróblewski, 1964, p. 11ff.

    Google Scholar 

  113. SC 16.03.1967 VI KZP 56/66 OSPIKA 1967 K 100.

    Google Scholar 

  114. SC 10.05.1967 III CZP 95/66 OSPIKA 1968 C 51.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Decisions of Social Insurance Tribunal: 01.03.1966 III TR 1600/65 OSPIKA 1967 U 279; 12.05.1966 I TR 2377/65 OSPIKA 1968 U 74.

    Google Scholar 

  116. SC 03.11.1964 I PR 326/64 OSPIKA 1967 C 27.

    Google Scholar 

  117. SC 19.02.1968 III CZP 40/76 OSPIKA 1968 C 197.

    Google Scholar 

  118. SC 13.12.1965 II KR 372/65 OSPIKA 1967 K 266 and the comment by Z. Papierkowski; SC 09.02.1967 V KRN 684/66 OSPIKA 1967 K 241 with the comment by A. Kubec.

    Google Scholar 

  119. In detail J. Wróblewski, 1961c.

    Google Scholar 

  120. SC 05.04.1967 IV KR 269/66 OSPIKA 1968 K 66 qualified as praeter legem in the comment by K. Lojewski; SC 30.05.1966 III PR 15/66 OSPIKA 1967 C 112 qualified as contra legem in the comment by W. Siedlecki; an analogous comment on SC 03.02.1966 I PR 66/65 OSPIKA 1967 C 176 by J. Lapierre; SC 26.09.1968 III CRN 209/68 OSPIKA 1969 C 125 by A. Dobrzanski. Commenting on SC 04.09.1967 I PR 23/67 OSPIKA 1969 C 5 Z Z. Radwanski, talks of the lack of any possibility of finding any legal justification. SC shows the inadmissibility of contra legem interpretation SC 21.12.1965 III CR 314/65 OSPIKA 1967 C 231.

    Google Scholar 

  121. S. Włodyka, 1971, 1984b, 1984c.

    Google Scholar 

  122. S. Wiodyka, 1984b, pp. 208–243, cf., note (VII)46.

    Google Scholar 

  123. SC 21.03.1964 III CR 322/63 OSPIKA 1965 C 87.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Z. Resich, 1984; S. Wiodyka, 1984b, pp. 243–274; 1984c, pp. 291–311.

    Google Scholar 

  125. J. Wróblewski, 1974e, pp. 56–59.

    Google Scholar 

  126. SC 25.08.1981 IV CR 269/81 OSPIKA 1983 C 86; SC 17.11.1982 III CZP 12/81 OSPIKA 1983 C 244; SC 30.08.1983 IV KR 153/83 OSPIKA 1984 K 97; SC 02.12.1982 IV CR 484/82 OSPIKA 1984 C 4 notices that the view of the Supreme Court “... has been approved of... in some scientific opinions”.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Sometimes this type of argument is used in SAC decisions, e.g., SAC 21.10.1983 II SA 1644/839 OSPIKA 1984 AA 48; SAC 05.05.1983 SA§Wr 182/83 OSPIKA 1984 AA 76. The Polish Constitutional Tribunal extensively uses scientific opinions and professors of law are invited as experts in quaestiones iuris. Cf., J. Wróblewski, 1989e, p. 16ff.

    Google Scholar 

  128. SC 26.02.1968 III CZP 101/67 OSPIKA 1969 C 29.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Cf., note (VII)68.

    Google Scholar 

  130. J. Wróblewski, 1963b, pp. 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  131. Cf., notes (VII) 68, 84, 88, 105, 106; (VIII)24, 25; WDS, Ch IX.3; The SC says that the principles in questions ought always to be taken into account and not only when the applied rules refer to them SC 13.01.1966 III CR 306/63 OSPIKA 1967 C 108.

    Google Scholar 

  132. Cf., notes (VII)22, 84, 85, 87, 105–109; (VIII)21, 24, 29, 30, 118; (IX)8, 9, 24, 25.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Rules of sport as criteria of illicit action SC 08.07.1968 II CR 216/68 OSPIKA 1969 C 163 with the comment by B. Lewaszkiewicz-Petrykowska.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Cf., note 36 above.

    Google Scholar 

  135. Because of that, the LSPP has evaluative character J. Wróblewski, 1982d, pp. 225–229; 1983b, p. 328ff; 1986e, p. 18ff. The LSPP conception in R. Dworkin’s version gives no possibility of any demarcation of law and non-law and this is linked with elimination of judicial discretion (J. Raz, 1984) but is favourable to judicial legislation (J. Mackie, 1984, p. 169).

    Google Scholar 

  136. Z. Niesiołowski and J. Rodziewicz, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  137. I have left out the case when the principle of legal system influences formulation of the rule of decision, because this situation has mixed features.

    Google Scholar 

  138. J. C. Hutcheson Jr 1938; scepticism concerning legal certainty, cf., J. Frank, 1949, pp. 73ff, 106, 159, 316, 321, 324 and a criticism, G. Gottlieb 1968. p. 23ff.

    Google Scholar 

  139. This corresponds with the conception of “situational ethics” or “ethics without code”, cf., M. Zirk-Sadowski, 1979, pp. 5–12.

    Google Scholar 

  140. S. S. Aleksiejew, 1973, p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  141. S. Wiodyka, 1984, p. 286.

    Google Scholar 

  142. S. S. Aleksiejew, 1973, Ch XXXI, 5.

    Google Scholar 

  143. S. Włodyka, 1984c, p. 287ff.

    Google Scholar 

  144. WDS, Ch IX.1.1.

    Google Scholar 

  145. ZTP, p. 113; L. Lombardi Vallauri, 1981, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  146. J. Wróblewski, 1985c.

    Google Scholar 

  147. S. Włodyka, 1984c, pp. 287–311.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Ch. Perelman and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, 1958, par 70; Ch. Perelman, 1979b, Ch 14; R. S. Summers, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  149. R. Dworkin’s views asserting the existence of the one right answer (e.g., R. Dworkin, 1985, Ch V) stimulated critical discussion. Cf., A. Aarnio, 1987, Ch IV; CGTIJ, Ch 7; J. Igartua, 1988; A. Peczenik, 1983, 1989, Ch 5, 9; J. Wróblewski, 1989c. A version of the theory of one right decision seems to be the idea behind “Angemessenheit” (K. Günther, 1988, pp. 9, 345–353) defined procedurally as “impartiality” (ibidem pp. 27.317, 320.341, 353).

    Google Scholar 

  150. Even the most authoritative decisions are not treated as uniquely right decisions S. Wiodyka, 1984b, p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  151. J. Wróblewski, 1988f, p. 360ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Zenon Bańkowski Neil MacCormick

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1992 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wróblewski, J. (1992). Rationality and the Correctness of a Decision of the Application of Law. In: Bańkowski, Z., MacCormick, N. (eds) The Judicial Application of Law. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 15. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8050-2_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8050-2_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4113-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8050-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics